Skip to main content
Log in

Can Culture Justify Infant Circumcision?

  • Winner of the PG Essay Prize
  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper addresses arguments in the recent philosophical and bioethical literature claiming that social and cultural benefits can justify non-therapeutic male infant circumcision. It rejects these claims by referring to the open future argument, according to which infant circumcision is morally unjustifiable because it violates the child’s right to an open future. The paper also addresses an important objection to the open future argument and examines the strength of the objection to refute the application of the argument to the circumcision case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Therefore, I imply what Judaism defines as milah, not periah. See Mazor (2013, pp. 421–428).

  2. An idea first espoused by Maimonides in twelfth century. See Gollaher (2001, pp. 19–30) and Glick (2005, pp. 64–66).

  3. Here, I assume a broad (sociological) understanding of religion, with no intention to discuss doctrinal issues. This understanding enables me to group metaphysical (first) with communal (second and third) claims. The distinction between ‘secular’ and ‘religious’ form of the cultural benefits argument should not be taken as too strict. It can be also framed as the difference between culture in the ‘broad’ sense and culture in the ‘narrow’ sense of the word. However, I opt for ‘secular’ versus ‘religious’ for the sake of simplicity.

  4. Though, as many authors report, there are surgical procedures that can restore the prepuce, they merely recover the aesthetic but not bodily functions of the foreskin. See Gollaher (2001) and Glick (2005).

References

  • American Academy of Pediatrics, Task Force on Circumcision. 2012. Circumcision policy statement. Pediatrics 130(3): 585–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Academy of Pediatrics, Task Force on Circumcision. 2013. The AAP task force on neonatal circumcision: A call for respectful dialogue. Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 442–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archard, David. 2002. Children, multiculturalism and education. In The moral and political status of children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod, 142–160. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, Michael, and David Benatar. 2003. Between prophylaxis and child abuse: The ethics of neonatal male circumcision. The American Journal of Bioethics 3(2): 35–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Yami, Hanoch. 2013. Circumcision: What should be done? Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 459–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Samantha. 2002. Children’s choices or children’s interests: Which do their rights protect? In The moral and political status of children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod, 53–70. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, Harry. 2002. What rights (if any) do children have? In The moral and political status of children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod, 31–53. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • British Medical Association. 2004. The law and ethics of male circumcision: Guidance for doctors. Journal of Medical Ethics 30(3): 259–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cannold, Leslie. 2006. The ethics of neonatal male circumcision: Helping parents to decide. In Cutting to the core: Exploring the ethics of contested surgeries, ed. David Benatar, 47–63. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Doriane Lambelet. 1998. The Seattle compromise: Multicultural sensitivity and Americanization. The Duke Law Journal 47: 717–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darby, Robert J.L. 2013. The child’s right to an open future: Is the principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision? Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 463–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Dena S. 1997a. The child’s right to open future: Yoder and beyond. Capital University Law Review 26: 93–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Dena S. 1997b. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 27(2): 7–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Dena S. 2013. Ancient rites and new laws: How should we regulate religious circumcision of minors? Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 456–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1992. The child’s right to open future. In Freedom and fulfillment: Philosophical essays, ed. Joel Feinberg, 76–98. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glick, Leonard B. 2005. Marked in your flesh: Circumcision from ancient Judea to modern America. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gollaher, David L. 2001. Circumcision: A history of the world’s most controversial surgery. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, James. 2002. Do children have rights? In The moral and political status of children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod, 19–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mazor, Joseph. 2013. The child’s interests and the case for permissibility of male infant circumcision. Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 421–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merkel, Reinhard, and Holm Putzke. 2013. After Cologne: Male circumcision and the law. Parental right, religious liberty or criminal assault? Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 444–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, J. 2005. Religious upbringing, religious diversity and the child’s right to an open future. Studies in Philosophy and Education 24: 367–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, Robert. 2002. Special agents: Children’s autonomy and parental authority. In The moral and political status of children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod, 97–118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Svoboda, J. Steven, Robert S. Van Howe, and James G. Dwyer. 2000. Informed consent for neonatal circumcision: An ethical and legal conundrum. Faculty Publications 167: 61–133.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Kerem Öktem, Sune Laegaard, and two anonymous reviewers for useful comments on earlier versions of this paper. This article is a part of the doctoral dissertation I defended at the Central European University in 2014, and has in part been funded by the Open Society Foundation through the “Signals from the Majority” project. I would also like to thank Central European University’s Department of Political Science, Columbia University’s Department of Political Science and Oxford University’s European Studies Centre for support during the research for this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eldar Sarajlic.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sarajlic, E. Can Culture Justify Infant Circumcision?. Res Publica 20, 327–343 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-014-9254-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-014-9254-x

Keywords

Navigation