Skip to main content
Log in

Data Fabrication and Falsification and Empiricist Philosophy of Science

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scientists have rules pertaining to data fabrication and falsification that are enforced with significant punishments, such as loss of funding, termination of employment, or imprisonment. These rules pertain to data that describe observable and unobservable entities. In this commentary I argue that scientists would not adopt rules that impose harsh penalties on researchers for data fabrication or falsification unless they believed that an aim of scientific research is to develop true theories and hypotheses about entities that exist, including unobservable ones. This argument presents a challenge for constructive empiricists, such as van Fraassen. Constructive empiricists need to be able to explain why rules pertaining to data fabrication and falsification do not threaten their philosophy of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bogen, J. (2009). Theory and observation in science. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/science-theory-observation/#DatPhe. Accessed November 9, 2012.

  • Bogen, J., & Woodward, J. (1988). Saving the phenomena. Philosophical Review, 97, 303–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bok, S. (1979). Lying: Moral choice in public and private life. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. N. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 19, 45–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cyranoski, D. (2006). Blow follows blow for stem-cell work. Nature, 439, 8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fanelli, D. (2009). How many scientists fabricate and falsify research? A systematic review and meta-analysis of survey data. PLoS One, 4, e5738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1996). The shaky game: Einstein, realism and the quantum theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1990). Science as a process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hwang, W. S., Roh, S. I., Lee, B. C., Kang, S. K., Kwon, D. K., Kim, S., et al. (2005). Patient-specific embryonic stem cells derived from human SCNT blastocysts. Science, 308, 1777–1783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hwang, W. S., Ryu, Y. J., Park, J. H., Park, E. S., Lee, E. G., Koo, J. M., et al. (2004). Evidence of a pluripotent human embryonic stem cell line derived from a cloned blastocyst. Science, 303, 1669–1674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1995). The advancement of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1980). The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Sciences and values. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Office of Science and Technology Policy. (2000). Federal research misconduct policy. Federal Register, 65(235), 76260–76264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D.B., & Dinse, G.E.  (2012).  Scientific corrections and retractions related to misconduct findings.  Journal of Medical Ethics, 39, 46–50. 

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D.B., Peddada, S., & Brunson Jr, W.  (2009).  Misconduct policies of scientific journals.  Accountability in Research, 16, 254–267.

  • Shamoo, A.S., & Resnik, D.B. (2009). Responsible conduct of research (2nd ed.).  New York: Oxford University Press.

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1985). Empiricism in the philosophy of science. In P. M. Churchland & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science (pp. 245–308). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (2001). Constructive empiricism now. Philosophical Studies, 106, 151–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. (1986). Arguments for scientific realism: The ascending spiral. American Philosophical Quarterly, 23, 287–298.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This article is the work product of an employee or group of employees of the National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences (NIEHS), National Institutes of Health (NIH). However, the statements, opinions or conclusions contained therein do not necessarily represent the statements, opinions or conclusions of NIEHS, NIH, or the United States government. I am grateful to Kevin Elliott and K. Brad Wray for reading earlier versions of this paper and providing useful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David B. Resnik.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Resnik, D.B. Data Fabrication and Falsification and Empiricist Philosophy of Science. Sci Eng Ethics 20, 423–431 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-013-9466-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-013-9466-z

Keywords

Navigation