Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
  • Cited by 42
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Online publication date:
February 2013
Print publication year:
2013
Online ISBN:
9781139179003

Book description

Is it allowable for your government, or anyone else, to influence or coerce you 'for your own sake'? This is a question about paternalism, or interference with a person's liberty or autonomy with the intention of promoting their good or averting harm, which has created considerable controversy at least since John Stuart Mill's On Liberty. Mill famously decried paternalism of any kind, whether carried out by private individuals or the state. In this volume of new essays, leading moral, political and legal philosophers address how to define paternalism, its justification, and the implications for public policy, professional ethics and criminal law. So-called 'libertarian' or non-coercive paternalism receives considerable attention. The discussion addresses the nature of freedom and autonomy and the relation of individuals to law, policy and the state. The volume will interest a wide range of readers in political philosophy, public policy and the philosophy of law.

Refine List

Actions for selected content:

Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Contents

  • Introduction - Paternalism – Issues and trends
    pp 1-24
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This introductory chapter discusses some of the key aspects of the present-day discussion of paternalism. Interest in paternalism has been heightened recently by the publication of Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein's Nudge. They tout an approach to policy-making that is at once paternalistic but will not offend its traditional (libertarian) critics. At the heart of Thaler and Sunstein's defense of libertarian paternalism is a body of psychological research showing that people's choices are influenced by small and apparently insignificant aspects of the choice environment, or what they call the choice architecture. There is a well-known objection to utilitarianism: insofar as it aims to maximize good in the aggregate, individuals can be sacrificed for the greater good. Paternalistic nudges risk harming a portion of the population. Thaler and Sunstein would presumably object to stacking nudges because collectively they might constitute a shove.
  • Chapter 1 - Defining paternalism
    pp 25-38
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter begins by canvassing a wide variety of definitions of paternalism which may have been developed in quite different contexts for quite different purposes. It is helpful both to see how wide the variety is and to see the various dimensions along which the definitions vary. A paternalistic act may be defined in terms of the outcomes it produces. The alternative view is that the reasons which count in determining whether an act is paternalistic are the hypothetical reasons which could motivate or justify the act. The first thing to note is that the entire discussion of paternalism takes place in the larger context of a discussion of the Unconscionability Doctrine (UD) in contract law. There is a normative dispute about the use of the doctrine. Liberals tend to favor it as a way of enabling poor people who are taken advantage of to get out of contractual obligations.
  • Chapter 2 - Penal paternalism
    pp 39-55
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter discusses the special problems that pertain to penal paternalism. The author's theory of criminalization consists in six constraints that must be satisfied before a penal law, any penal law, may be enacted and enforced. First, all criminal laws must be designed to prevent harm. Second, the conduct proscribed by the criminal law must be wrongful. Third, persons must deserve punishment for violating the criminal law. Fourth, the state must have a substantial interest in proscribing the conduct banned by a criminal law. Fifth, the law must actually promote that state interest. Sixth, the law must be no more extensive than necessary to accomplish its purpose. The chapter describes several problems in efforts to show that a given instance of penal paternalism satisfies them. The problem facing paternalists is to decide whether the wrongs involved in failures to take care of oneself are public or private.
  • Chapter 3 - Self-sovereignty and paternalism
    pp 56-73
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Mill's aim in using the metaphor of sovereignty was presumably to suggest that the government ought to respect the autonomy of each individual unless he poses a threat to others, just as a nation ought to respect the sovereignty of another nation unless it poses a threat to another nation. The choice to use illicit drugs involves important forms of discretionary control over one's own mind and body. Non-legalization might still violate the opportunity principle because the choice to use drugs involves important forms of control over mind and body, and this policy reduces the opportunities to make this choice. It is possible to respect self-sovereignty and to give a plausible theory of its boundaries without endorsing a general principle of anti-paternalism like Mill's harm principle. So, the importance of self-sovereignty provides no reason to think that paternalism is always wrong.
  • Chapter 4 - The right to autonomy and the justification of hard paternalism
    pp 74-92
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter critically examines some different views about the content, strength, and justification of a right to autonomy. It explains some background assumptions about the right to autonomy, the concept of paternalism, and the soft/hard distinction. There are two basic approaches to spelling out the content of the right: choice-based and preference-based. Joel Feinberg's view that the right protects only self-regarding choices that are voluntary enough is one example of the former. The claim that the right is absolute vis-à-vis moralistic reasons mean that when moralistic interference infringes the right to autonomy, it is always wrong. If the right to autonomy is cashed out in terms of a hybrid current preferences account (CP) test, then an example of soft moralism might be one orthodox Jew's forcing a second to wait to eat till his craving for a delicious but non-kosher food passes.
  • Chapter 5 - Moral environmentalism
    pp 93-114
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter characterizes the moral environmentalism and presents a presumptive case for it. The autonomy objection to moral environmentalism is then outlined. Moral environmentalism is also an instance of legal paternalism. The moral environmentalist proposes to use the law, including its coercive apparatus, to create or preserve an emotional and cultural climate that favors some forms of life over others. Moral environmentalism aims to bring about a moral environment that will best enable the members of a society, in general, to lead morally valuable lives. The author concerns with one influential objection to moral environmentalism. This objection appeals directly to the value of personal autonomy. The appeal to autonomy is the most influential line of resistance to moral environmentalism at the level of moral principle, but other lines of resistance may prove to be more promising than the author has realized.
  • Chapter 6 - Kantian paternalism and suicide intervention
    pp 115-133
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Kantian paternalism (KP) allows for paternalistic interference in order to help agents achieve the rationally chosen ends that constitute their conception of the good. It offers a necessary condition on paternalistic interference because it recognizes that the moral and non-moral costs of such interference can sometimes outweigh its benefits. Central to KP is the notion that paternalism is warranted when agents exhibit a certain form of instrumental irrationality. Intuitively, there is a difference between an agent irrationally choosing inadequate means to her chosen end and an irrational agent choosing inadequate means to her chosen end. The main normative power is the power of instrumental rationality, the power to determine the most effective means to the ends that constitute the conception of the good. Characterizations of rational suicide treat an individual's interests in a realist manner, as if what constitutes an individual's interests is wholly independent of her actual attitudes.
  • Chapter 7 - Paternalism and the principle of fairness
    pp 134-156
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter has defended the Hart-Rawls principles of fairness as justifying the duty to obey the law, in a broad range of cases. It contributes towards the development of the most promising non-consequentialist moral theory. Robert Nozick's examples include some in which a non-excludable good is provided to a group of people. He imagines a neighborhood public address system, with individuals taking turns entertaining their neighbors through loudspeakers that blare sound throughout the neighborhood day and night. The Hart-Rawls principle of fairness has attracted still an objection. This claims the principle is objectionably paternalist. The paternalism objection directly attacks the principle of fairness, and a fortiori attacks any attempt to deploy the principle of fairness to show how people come to be obligated to contribute to the support of the state in which they reside and to obey the laws of a tolerably decent state.
  • Chapter 8 - Paternalism in economics
    pp 157-177
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Economists are notoriously averse to paternalism. Happiness-driven economics (HDE) has been widely accused of paternalism, particularly by friends of minimalism. The question of paternalism in HDE raises broader questions about the potential for paternalism in economic policy analysis. This chapter begins with a characterization of minimalism. Then, using a broad definition of paternalism, the chapter examines the anti-paternalist credentials of minimalism and find them wanting. It considers how policy-makers might avoid, or at least minimize, paternalism, arguing that HDE should be part of a less paternalistic approach to policy analysis. Minimalist cost-benefit analysis (MCBA)-based policy threatens paternalism not just for farmers and fishermen, but for those subject to any policy with highly disruptive effects on people's lives. The central charge against minimalist economics is moral incoherence, specifically where that framework extends to the policy realm for weighing the costs and benefits of policy options.
  • Chapter 9 - Choice Architecture: A mechanism for improving decisions while preserving liberty?
    pp 178-196
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Ethical arguments for creating choice environments that lead people to make better choices revolve around two claims: it makes people better off, and it does so in a way that is entirely compatible with individual liberty. This chapter examines these two claims. The first half of the chapter turns to the conceptual and normative concerns with the claim that choice architecture makes people better off. The second half of the chapter turns to the soundness of the claim that choice architecture is compatible with liberty. Decision-making or advising others often generates a critical attitude that is not always engendered when we decide for ourselves. One way to combat choice architecture hindering the exercise of autonomy is to make it transparent to those who encounter it. In order to fully preserve liberty choice architecture must not block off or significantly burden other choices.
  • Chapter 10 - A psychological defense of paternalism
    pp 197-215
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Economists are traditionally hostile to paternalism; public policy-makers and legal academics tend to be as well. Traditional objections to paternalism center on individual autonomy and the freedom to choose, on individuals' ability to learn from their mistakes, and on knowledge problems to which central planners are subject. More recently, in response to empirical demonstrations that people are vulnerable to a variety of cognitive and emotional biases in decision-making, anti-paternalists suggest that such central planners or experts are just as vulnerable. Each of these objections, though superficially plausible, nevertheless is challenged by empirical findings in psychology and cognitive science. Part of the objection to paternalistic interventions stems from traditional assumptions about the evils of paternalistic intervention per se. The strongest traditional assumption is the libertarian perspective that individuals know their own preferences and are better than any third party at choosing among alternatives to obtain the appropriate outcome.
  • Chapter 11 - Libertarian paternalism, utilitarianism, and justice
    pp 216-230
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter argues that the empirical evidence cited by the authors, Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler is capable of supporting a number of competing approaches, including what the author calls libertarian utilitarianism and libertarian justice. Central to Sunstein and Thaler's proposal is their claim that evidence from the social sciences justifies a distinctively paternalistic approach to public policy. The chapter considers three different arguments purporting to justify the use of a paternalist approach to public policy. The first argument comes from a series of publications by Sunstein and Thaler written prior to Nudge. The second reconstructs the argument of Nudge, where the authors merely claim that nudges are inevitable. Finally, the third provides a friendly argument, intended to establish that nudges ought to be paternalistic. This chapter uses an empirical evidence of framing effects to construct nudges aimed at promoting Rawls' theory of justice.
  • Chapter 12 - Voluntary enslavement
    pp 231-246
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Abel is a poor man in a Third- World country. He gets by, barely, by acting as an all-purpose guide for rich Westerners on vacation. Baker, a very rich American, hires Abel as a guide and is very impressed with the multitude of skills Abel displays over the several days of their relationship. This chapter provides an Abel-Baker scenario, which raises the issue of contracting into slavery. Anthony Kronman assimilates voluntary enslavement to all contracts that call for the performance of personal services as opposed to the delivery of goods or money. There are several types of voluntarily acquired legally enforceable affirmative duties to perform services. Disappointment can occur whenever performance of a contract fails to achieve what the contractors believed would be achieved. The possibility of disappointment is surely no bar to the enforcement of promises, for that possibility attends all promissory obligations.
  • Chapter 13 - Paternalism, (school) choice, and opportunity
    pp 247-265
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter argues that paternalism can be a reasonable component of certain social policies directed at adults, focusing on school choice as a key example. It suggests that contrary to the common depiction of paternalism as antithetical to choice, the two policy tools can sometimes supplement each other in productive ways. One key area that generates debates on paternalism, choice, and opportunities is the many policies lumped together under the heading "school choice". The discussion of the Philadelphia school-choice system focuses on the promise that choice would improve equality, and the discussion of the DC program focuses on the promise that school choice would allow families to freely express their preferences. One of the most significant findings arising from the evaluations of opportunity scholarships program (OSP) has to do with the importance of information.
Bibliography
Adler, M. D., and Posner, E. A.. New Foundations of Cost–Benefit Analysis. Harvard University Press, 2006.
Adler, M. D., and Posner, E. A., eds. Cost–Benefit Analysis: Economic, Philosophical, and Legal Perspectives. University of Chicago Press Journals, 2001.
AETNA. “Aetna Announces New Weight Management Program at National Summit on Obesity,” June 3, 2004. .
Alexandrova, A., and Haybron, D. M.. “High-Fidelity Economics.” In Hands, W. H. and Davis, J. B., eds., The Elgar Companion to Recent Economic Methodology. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar, 2012, 94–120.
Anderson, E. S. Value in Ethics and Economics. Harvard University Press, 1995.
Anderson, E. S. “What Is the Point of Equality?”Ethics 109 (1999): 287–337.
André-Bechely, L. Could It Be Otherwise?: Parents and the Inequalities of Public School Choice. London: Routledge, 2005.
ANES. “ANES Guide to Public Opinion and Electoral Behavior: Government Guaranteed Job/Standard of Living (1) 1956–2002,” 2005. .
Angner, E.“Economists as Experts: Overconfidence in Theory and Practice.”Journal of Economic Methodology 13 (2006): 1–24.
Anscombe, G. E. M.“Modern Moral Philosophy.”Philosophy 33 (1958): 1–19.
Ariely, D., and Wertenbroch, K.. “Procrastination, Deadlines, and Performance: Self-Control by Precommitment.”Psychological Science 13 (2002): 219–224.
Arneson, R. J.“Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism.”Legal Theory 11 (2005): 259–284.
Arneson, R. J.“Mill Versus Paternalism.”Ethics 90 (1980): 470–489.
Arneson, R. J.“Paternalism, Utility, and Fairness.” In Dworkin, G., ed., Mill’s On Liberty: Critical Essays. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997, 83–114.
Arneson, R. J.“Perfectionism and Politics.”Ethics 111 (2000): 37–63.
Arneson, R. J.“The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems.”Ethics 92 (1982): 616–633.
Arneson, R. J.“What, If Anything, Renders All Humans Morally Equal?” In Jameson, D., ed., Singer and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999, 103–128.
Baron, J., and Spranca, M. D.. “Protected Values.”Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 70 (1997): 1–16.
Baron, M.“Manipulativeness.”Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 77 (2003): 37–54.
Baron, R. A.Essentials of Psychology. 3rd edn. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon, 2001.
Barrotta, P.“Why Economists Should Be Unhappy with the Economics of Happiness.”Economics and Philosophy 24 (2008): 145–165.
Barrow, L., and Rouse, C. E.. “School Vouchers: Recent Findings and Unanswered Questions.”Economic Perspectives 32 (2008): 2–16.
Battin, M. P.“Can Suicide Be Rational? Yes, Sometimes.” In Werth, J. L., ed., Contemporary Perspectives on Rational Suicide. Oxford: Taylor & Francis, 1999, 13–21.
Beattie, J., Baron, J., Hershey, J. C., and Spranca, M. D.. “Psychological Determinants of Decision Attitude.”Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 7 (1994): 129–144.
Ben-Porath, S. R. “Race, Choice and Opportunity.” Forthcoming in Theory and Research in Education.
Ben-Porath, S. R.Tough Choices: Structured Paternalism and the Landscape of Choice. Princeton University Press, 2010.
Berlin, I.“Two Concepts of Liberty.” In Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University Press, 1969, 118–172.
Berry, W.“An Argument for Diversity.” In Berry, W., ed., What Are People For?New York: North Point Press, 1990, 109–122.
Blumenthal, J. A.“Does Mood Influence Moral Judgment? An Empirical Test with Legal and Policy Implications.”Law & Psychology Review 29 (2005): 1–28.
Blumenthal, J. A.“Emotional Paternalism.”Florida State University Law Review 35 (2007): 1–72.
Blumenthal, J. A. “Expert Paternalism.” Florida Law Review 64 (2012): 721–757.
Blumenthal, J. A.“Law and the Emotions: The Problems of Affective Forecasting.”Indiana Law Journal 80 (2005): 155–238.
Blumenthal, J. A., and Huang, P. H.. “Positive Parentalism.” The National Law Journal (2009): 27.
Bok, D.The Politics of Happiness: What Government Can Learn from the New Research on Well-Being. Princeton University Press, 2010.
Bouwsma, O. K., and Wittgenstein, L.. Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949–1951. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1986.
Bradley, B.Well-Being and Death. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Brandt, R. B.“The Morality and Rationality of Suicide.” In Perlin, S., ed., A Handbook for the Study of Suicide. Oxford University Press, 1975, 61–75.
Bratman, M. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Harvard University Press, 1987.
Brighouse, H.School Choice and Social Justice. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Brock, D. W.“Paternalism and Autonomy.”Ethics 98 (1988): 550–565.
Broome, J.“Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?”Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 321–337.
Burrows, P.“Patronising Paternalism.”Oxford Economic Papers 45 (1993): 542–572.
Calcott, P.“Paternalism and Public Choice.”Victoria Economic Commentaries (2000): 39–46.
Camerer, C., Issacharoff, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T., and Rabin, M.. “Regulation for Conservatives: Behavioral Economics and the Case for ‘Asymmetric Paternalism’.”University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151 (2003): 1211–1254.
Carothers, A.“Letter from Costa Rica.”E Magazine, September 1993.
Cavanagh, J. T. O., Carson, A. J., Sharpe, M., and Lawrie, S. M.. “Psychological Autopsy Studies of Suicide: A Systematic Review.”Psychological Medicine 33 (2003): 395–405.
Cave, E. M.“What’s Wrong with Motive Manipulation?”Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (2007): 129–144.
Center for Health Transformation. “Healthcare That Works: Answering President Obama’s Challenge of Finding What Works.” Center for Health Transformation. .
Cholbi, M. J.“A Kantian Defense of Prudential Suicide.”Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (2010): 489–515.
Cholbi, M. J.“Depression, Listlessness, and Moral Motivation.”Ratio 24 (2011): 28–45.
Cholbi, M. J.“Suicide Intervention and Non-Ideal Kantian Theory.”Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2002): 245–259.
Cholbi, M. J.Suicide: The Philosophical Dimensions. Buffalo, NY: Broadview Press, 2011.
Chubb, J. E., and Moe, T. M.. Politics, Markets, and America’s Schools. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, 1990.
Clarke, S.“A Definition of Paternalism.”Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5 (2002): 81–91.
Cohen, G. A.“Self-Ownership, World Ownership, and Equality.” In Lucash, F. S., ed., Justice and Equality Here and Now. Cornell University Press, 1986, 108–135.
Cowley, C.“Suicide Is Neither Rational Nor Irrational.”Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (2006): 495–504.
CREDO. “Multiple Choice: Charter School Performance in 16 States.” Center for Research on Education Outcomes, 2009. .
Criddle, E. J.“Fiduciary Administration: Rethinking Popular Representation in Agency Rulemaking.”Texas Law Review 88 (2010): 441–503.
Criddle, E. J.“Fiduciary Foundations of Administrative Law.”UCLA Law Review 54 (2006): 117–183.
Cullity, G.“Moral Free Riding.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 24 (1995): 3–34.
Cushman, F., Young, L., and Greene, J. D.. “Our Multi-System Moral Psychology: Towards a Consensus View.” In Doris, J., ed., The Moral Psychology Handbook. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010, 47–71.
de Marneffe, P.“Avoiding Paternalism.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 34 (2006): 68–94.
de Marneffe, P.Liberalism and Prostitution. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Devine, P.“On Choosing Death.” In Battin, M. P. and Mayo, D. J., eds., Suicide: The Philosophical Issues. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1980, 138–143.
Diener, E., Lucas, R., Schimmack, U., and Helliwell, J.. Well-Being for Public Policy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Dodenhoff, D.“Fixing the Milwaukee Public Schools: The Limits of Parent-Driven Reform.”Wisconsin Policy Research Institute 5 (2007).
Dolan, P., and White, M. P.. “How Can Measures of Subjective Well-Being Be Used to Inform Public Policy?”Perspectives on Psychological Science 2 (2007): 71–85.
Durant, W.The Story of Philosophy. Eastsound, WA: Turtleback Press, 1991.
Dworkin, G.Mill’s On Liberty: Critical Essays. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997.
Dworkin, G.“Paternalism.”The Monist 56 (1972): 64–84.
Dworkin, G. “Paternalism.” In E. N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2010. .
Dworkin, G.“Paternalism: Some Second Thoughts.” In Sartorius, R., ed., Paternalism. University of Minnesota Press, 1982, 105–112.
Dworkin, G.The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Dworkin, R.Justice for Hedgehogs. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011.
Dwyer, J. G.“Changing the Conversation About Children’s Education.” In Macedo, S. and Tamir, Y., eds., Moral and Political Education. New York University Press, 2002, 314–358.
Edwards, C.“Beyond Mental Competence.”Journal of Applied Philosophy 27 (2010): 273–289.
Ellerman, D.“Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice.”Law and Philosophy 29 (2010): 571–599.
Estlund, D. M. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton University Press, 2007.
Farnsworth, E. A.Contracts. 4th edn. New York: Aspen, 2004.
Feinberg, J.Harm to Others. New York: Oxford University Press, 1987.
Feinberg, J.Harm to Self. Oxford University Press, 1986.
Feinberg, J.“Legal Paternalism.” In Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty. Princeton University Press, 1980, 110–129.
Figlio, D. N., and Hart, C.. Competitive Effects of Means-Tested School Vouchers. Evanston, IL: National Bureau of Economic Research, 2010.
Fleurbaey, M. “The Importance of What People Care About.” Forthcoming in Politics, Philosophy and Economics.
Forgeard, M. J. C., Jayawickreme, E., Kern, M. L., and Seligman, M. E. P.. “Doing the Right Thing: Measuring Well-Being for Public Policy.”International Journal of Wellbeing 1 (2011): 79–106.
Foster, E. “Here Come Catch Shares: How NOAA and the Environmental Defense Fund Plan to Destroy North Carolina’s Working Watermen.”Island Free Press, November 10, 2010.
Fox-Decent, E.Sovereignty’s Promise: The State as Fiduciary. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Frankfurt, H.“Reply to John Martin Fischer.” In Buss, S. and Overton, L., eds., Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002, 27–31.
Frey, B. S. Happiness: A Revolution in Economics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008.
Galenson, D. W.“The Rise and Fall of Indentured Servitude in the Americas: An Economic Analysis.”The Journal of Economic History 44 (1984): 1–26.
Gallup Organization. Survey by Gallup Organization, May 2–May 8, 1988. Gallup Poll, May 1988. iPOLL Databank, The Roper Center for Public Opinion Research, University of Connecticut. .
Gert, B., and Culver, C. M.. “The Justification of Paternalism.”Ethics 89 (1979): 199–210.
Gilbert, D. T.Stumbling on Happiness. New York: Knopf, 2006.
Gilbert, D. T., and Ebert, J. E. J.. “Decisions and Revisions: The Affective Forecasting of Changeable Outcomes.”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 82 (2002): 503–514.
Gilbert, D. T., Gill, M. J., and Wilson, T. D.. “The Future Is Now: Temporal Correction in Affective Forecasting.”Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 88 (2002): 430–444.
Gilbert, D. T., and Wilson, T. D.. “Miswanting: Some Problems in the Forecasting of Future Affective States.” In Forgas, J., ed., Feeling and Thinking: The Role of Affect in Social Cognition. Cambridge University Press, 2000, 178–196.
Gilles, S. G.“On Educating Children: A Parentalist Manifesto.”University of Chicago Law Review 63 (1996): 937–1034.
Gillette, C. P., and Krier, J. E.. “Risk, Courts, and Agencies.”University of Pennsylvania Law Review 138 (1990): 1027–1109.
Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., and Kahneman, D., eds. Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Giordano, R., and Hardy, D.. “School Choice Gains Widespread Momentum.” Philly.com, January 31, 2011. .
Glaeser, E. L. “The Moral Heart of Economics.” The New York Times Economix Blog, January 25, 2011. .
Glaeser, E. L.“Paternalism and Psychology.”University of Chicago Law Review 73 (2006): 133–156.
Gleason, P., and Silverberg, M., National Center for Education Evaluation, Regional Assistance (US), and Institute of Education Sciences (US). The Evaluation of Charter School Impacts: Final Report. National Center for Education Evaluation and Regional Assistance, Institute of Education Sciences, US Department of Education, 2010.
Gold, J. L.“Paternalistic or Protective? Freedom of Expression and Direct-to-Consumer Drug Advertising Policy in Canada.”Health Law Review 11 (2003): 30–38.
Graber, G.“The Rationality of Suicide.” In Wallace, S. and Eser, A., eds., Suicide and Euthanasia: The Rights of Personhood. University of Tennessee Press, 1981, 51–65.
Green, D. P., and Gerken, A. E.. “Self-Interest and Public Opinion Toward Smoking Restrictions and Cigarette Taxes.”Public Opinion Quarterly 53 (1989): 1–16.
Greene, J. P.Education Myths: What Special Interest Groups Want You to Believe About Our Schools – and Why It Isn’t So. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2005.
Greenspan, P.“The Problem with Manipulation.”American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (2003): 155–164.
Grill, K.“Anti-Paternalism and Invalidation of Reasons.”Public Reason 2 (2010): 3–20.
Grill, K. “Anti-Paternalism and Public Health Policy.” Ph.D. thesis, Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm, 2009.
Grill, K.“The Normative Core of Paternalism.”Res Publica 13 (2007): 441–458.
Gul, F., and Pesendorfer, W.. “The Case for Mindless Economics.” In Caplin, A. and Schotter, A., eds., The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics: A Handbook. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008, 3–42.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., and Wistrich, A. J.. “Blinking on the Bench: How Judges Decide Cases.”Cornell Law Review 93 (2007): 1–43.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., and Wistrich, A. J.. “Inside the Judicial Mind.”Cornell Law Review 86 (2001): 777–867.
Gutmann, A.Democratic Education. Princeton University Press, 1999.
Gutmann, A.“How Limited Is Liberal Government?” In Yack, B., ed., Liberalism Without Illusions: Essays on Liberal Theory and the Political Vision of Judith N. Shklar. University of Chicago Press, 1996, 64–81.
Halpern, J., and Arnold, R. M.. “Affective Forecasting: An Unrecognized Challenge in Making Serious Health Decisions.”Journal of General Internal Medicine 23 (2008): 1708–1712.
Interactive, Harris. “The Harris Poll #10, CDC, FAA, NIH, FDA, FBI and USDA Get the Highest Ratings of Thirteen Federal Government Agencies,” February 6, 2007. .
Interactive, Harris.“The Harris Poll #30, Closing the Budget Deficit: U.S. Adults Strongly Resist Raising Any Taxes Except ‘Sin Taxes’ or Cutting Major Programs,” April 10, 2007. .
Interactive, Harris. “The Harris Poll #149, Oil, Pharmaceutical, Health Insurance, and Tobacco Top the List Of Industries That People Think Should Be More Regulated,” December 2, 2010. .
Hausman, D. M., and McPherson, M. S.. Economic Analysis, Moral Philosophy, and Public Policy. Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Hausman, D. M., and Welch, B.. “Debate: To Nudge or Not to Nudge.”Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (2010): 123–136.
Haybron, D. M.The Pursuit of Unhappiness: The Elusive Psychology of Well-Being. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Herman, B.“Transforming Incentives: Feelings and the Making of the Kantian Moral Agent.” In Carslon, A, ed., Philosophical Aspects on Emotions. Stockholm: Thales, 2005, Section 3.
Hess, F. M. “Does School Choice ‘Work’?” National Affairs, no. 5 (2010). .
Hibbing, J. R., and Theiss-Morse, E.. Stealth Democracy: Americans’ Beliefs About How Government Should Work. Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Hodson, J. D.“The Principle of Paternalism.”American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 61–69.
Hospers, J.“What Libertarianism Is.” In Machan, T., ed., The Libertarian Alternative. New York: Nelson Hall, 1974, 3–20.
Huang, P. H.“Authentic Happiness, Self-Knowledge and Legal Policy.”Minnesota Journal of Science and Technology 9 (2008): 755–784.
Huang, P. H., and Blumenthal, J. A.. “Positive Law and Policy.”Encyclopedia of Positive Psychology 2 (2009): 730–732.
Hurd, H. M.“Paternalism on Pain of Punishment.”Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (2009): 49–73.
Husak, D.“Convergent Ends, Divergent Means: A Response to My Critics.”Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (2009): 119–134.
Husak, D.Drugs and Rights. Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Husak, D.“Legal Paternalism.” In LaFollette, H., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics. Oxford University Press, 2003, 387–412.
Husak, D.Legalize This!: The Case for Decriminalizing Drugs. Brooklyn, NY: Verso Books, 2002.
Husak, D.Overcriminalization: The Limits of the Criminal Law. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Husak, D.“Paternalism.” Forthcoming in Marmor, A, ed., The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law. London: Routledge.
Husak, D.“Paternalism and Autonomy.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 10 (1981): 27–46.
Husak, D.“Paternalism and Consent.” In Miller, F. G. and Wertheimer, A., eds., The Ethics of Consent: Theory and Practice. Oxford University Press, 2010, 107–130.
Husak, D.“Recreational Drugs and Paternalism.”Law and Philosophy 8 (1989): 353–381.
Husak, D., and de Marneffe, P.. The Legalization of Drugs. Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Iyengar, S. S., and Lepper, M. R.. “Choice and Its Consequences: On the Costs and Benefits of Self-Determination.” In Tesser, A., Stapel, D. A., and Wood, J. V., eds., Self and Motivation: Emerging Psychological Perspectives. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2002, 71–96.
Iyengar, S. S., and Lepper, M. R.. “When Choice Is Demotivating: Can One Desire Too Much of a Good Thing?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 79 (2000): 995–1006.
Jacobson, D.“Utilitarianism Without Consequentialism: The Case of John Stuart Mill.”Philosophical Review 117 (2008): 159–191.
Jamison, K. R.Night Falls Fast: Understanding Suicide. New York: Vintage Books, 2000.
Joiner, T. Why People Die by Suicide. Harvard University Press, 2005.
Jolls, C., Sunstein, C. R., and Thaler, R. H.. “A Behavioral Approach to Law and Economics.”Stanford Law Review 50 (1998): 1471–1550.
Kahneman, D.“Maps of Bounded Rationality: Psychology for Behavioral Economics.”The American Economic Review 93 (2003): 1449–1475.
Kahneman, D.Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2011.
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., and Thaler, R. H., “Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion and Status Quo Bias.” In Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A., eds., Choices, Values, and Frames. Cambridge University Press, 2000, 159–170.
Kahneman, D., Krueger, A. B., Schkade, D., Schwarz, N., and Stone, A.. “Toward National Well-Being Accounts.”The American Economic Review 94 (2004): 429–434.
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A., eds. Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Kahneman, D., and Tversky, A., eds. Choices, Values, and Frames. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Kahneman, D., Wakker, P. P., and Sarin, R.. “Back to Bentham? Explorations of Experienced Utility.”The Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (1997): 375–406.
Permanente, Kaiser. “Kaiser Permanente Colorado Offers Its Employees incentaHEALTH Weight Loss and Wellness Program for Fourth Consecutive Year,” February 7, 2007. .
Kaustia, M., Alho, E., and Puttonen, V.. “How Much Does Expertise Reduce Behavioral Biases? The Case of Anchoring Effects in Stock Return Estimates.”Financial Management 37 (2008): 391–412.
Kelly, J. T. Framing Democracy: A Behavioral Approach to Democratic Theory. Forthcoming from Princeton University Press.
Klein, D. B.“Statist Quo Bias.”Econ Journal Watch 1 (2004): 260–271.
Kleinig, J. Paternalism. Manchester University Press, 1983.
Klick, J., and Mitchell, G.. “Government Regulation of Irrationality: Moral and Cognitive Hazards.”Minnesota Law Review 90 (2005): 1620–1663.
Klosko, G.Political Obligations. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Klosko, G.The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1992.
Knack, S.“Election-Day Registration: The Second Wave.”American Politics Research 29 (2001): 65–78.
Korobkin, R.“Bounded Rationality, Standard Form Contracts, and Unconscionability.”University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 1203–1295.
Korobkin, R., and Guthrie, C.. “Psychology, Economics, and Settlement: A New Look at the Role of the Lawyer.”Texas Law Review 76 (1997): 77–141.
Kray, L., and Gonzalez, R.. “Differential Weighting in Choice Versus Advice: I’ll Do This, You Do That.”Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 12 (1999): 207–218.
Krier, J. E.“Risk and Design.”The Journal of Legal Studies 19 (1990): 781–790.
Kronman, A. T.“Paternalism and the Law of Contracts.”The Yale Law Journal 92 (1983): 763–798.
Kronman, A. T.“Specific Performance.”The University of Chicago Law Review 45 (1978): 351–382.
Kyritsis, D.“Representation and Waldron’s Objection to Judicial Review.”Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (2006): 733–751.
Larmore, C. E. Patterns of Moral Complexity. Cambridge University Press, 1987.
Layard, R.Happiness: Lessons from a New Science. New York: The Penguin Press HC, 2005.
Leenaars, A. A.Suicide Notes: Predictive Clues and Patterns. New York: Human Sciences Press, 1988.
Levi, M., and Stoker, L.. “Political Trust and Trustworthiness.”Annual Review of Political Science 3 (2000): 475–507.
Levinson, Meira. The Demands of Liberal Education. Oxford University Press, 1999.
Locke, J.Two Treatises of Government. London: Awnsham Churchill, 1690.
Loewenstein, G., and Haisley, E.. “The Economist as Therapist: Methodological Ramifications of ‘Light’ Paternalism.” In Caplin, A. and Schotter, A., eds., Perspectives on the Future of Economics: Positive and Normative Foundations, Vol. i. The Handbook of Economic Methodologies. Oxford University Press, 2008, 210–248.
Loewenstein, G., and Schkade, D.. “Wouldn’t It Be Nice? Predicting Future Feelings.” In Kahneman, D., Diener, E., and Schwarz, N., eds., Well-Being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology. New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1999, 85–107.
Loewenstein, G., and Ubel, P. A.. “Hedonic Adaptation and the Role of Decision and Experience Utility in Public Policy.”Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008): 1795–1810.
Luper, S. The Philosophy of Death. Cambridge University Press, 2009.
Macey, J. R.“Transaction Costs and the Normative Elements of the Public Choice Model: An Application to Constitutional Theory.”Virginia Law Review 74 (1988): 471–518.
MacIntyre, A. A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century. 2nd edn. University of Notre Dame Press, 1998.
MADD. Survey by MADD, Nationwide Insurance and Gallup Organization, July 26–August 14, 2005. MADD, 2005. iPOLL Databank, The Roper Center for Public Opinion Research, University of Connecticut. .
Martinez, M. D., and Hill, D.. “Did Motor Voter Work?”American Politics Research 27 (1999): 296–315.
McCabe, D. Modus Vivendi Liberalism: Theory and Practice. Cambridge University Press, 2010.
McDowell, J.“Virtue and Reason in the Concept of a Person in Ethical Theory.”The Monist 62 (1979): 331–350.
McNeil, B. J., Pauker, S. G., Sox, Jr. H. C., and Tversky, A.. “On the Elicitation of Preferences for Alternative Therapies.”New England Journal of Medicine 306 (1982): 1259–1262.
Mele, A. R.Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Mello, M. M., Rimm, E. B., and Studdert, D. M.. “The McLawsuit: The Fast-Food Industry and Legal Accountability for Obesity.”Health Affairs 22 (2003): 207–216.
Mello, M. M., Studdert, D. M., and Brennan, T. A.. “Obesity – the New Frontier of Public Health Law.”New England Journal of Medicine 354 (2006): 2601–2610.
Mengisen, A. “From Push to Nudge: A Q&A With the Authors of the Latter.” Freakonomics: The Hidden Side of Everything, April 15, 2008. .
Merrill, T. W.“Rethinking Article I, Section I: From Nondelegation to Exclusive Delegation.”Columbia Law Review 104 (2004): 2097–2181.
Mill, J. S.On Liberty, ed. Rapaport, E.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1978.
Mill, J. S.Utilitarianism, ed. Sher, G.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2001.
Mitchell, G.“Libertarian Paternalism Is an Oxymoron.”Northwestern University Law Review 99 (2005): 1245–1277.
Mohanty, M.“Small Farmers and Doha Round: Lessons from Mexico’s NAFTA Experience.”La Chronique Des Amériques 12 (2008).
Monahan, A. B.“Addressing the Problem of Impatients, Impulsives and Other Imperfect Actors in 401 (k) Plans.”Virginia Tax Review 23 (2004): 471–529.
Motto, J. A.“The Right to Suicide: A Psychiatrist’s View.”Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 2 (1972): 183–188.
Nagel, T. Equality and Partiality. Oxford University Press, 1991.
National High School Center. “The First Year of High School: A Quick Stats Fact Sheet,” March 2007. .
Neatby, S. “Hard Times Sold in Vending Machines: Worker Migration from Atlantic Canada to the Tar Sands.” The Dominion, January 8, 2008. .
Noggle, R.“Manipulative Actions: A Conceptual and Moral Analysis.”American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1996): 43–55.
Notebook, The. “Choosing a High School,” 2011. .
Nozick, R. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books, 1974.
Nussbaum, M. C.“The Costs of Tragedy: Some Moral Limits of Cost–Benefit Analysis.”The Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000): 1005–1036.
Ofir, C.“Ease of Recall vs. Recalled Evidence in Judgment: Experts vs. Laymen.”Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 81 (2000): 28–42.
Orr, S. W.“Values, Preferences, and the Citizen–Consumer Distinction in Cost–Benefit Analysis.”Politics, Philosophy & Economics 6 (2007): 107–130.
Paige, R. “A Time for Choice: Remarks at the Heritage Foundation,” January 28, 2004. .
Parfit, D.On What Matters, Vol. i. Oxford University Press, 2011.
Parfit, D.Reasons and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.
Pettit, P.“Free Riding and Foul Dealing.”The Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 361–379.
Pilpel, A., and Amsel, L.. “What Is Wrong with Rational Suicide.”Philosophia 39 (2011): 111–123.
Pope, T. M.“Counting the Dragon’s Teeth and Claws: The Definition of Hard Paternalism.”Georgia State University Law Review 20 (2004): 659–722.
Pope, T. M.“Is Public Health Paternalism Really Never Justified? A Response to Joel Feinberg.”Oklahoma City University Law Review 30 (2005): 121–207.
Postrel, V. I.“Paternalism Test: Regulation Is the Real Test of the ‘anti-Government’ Mood.”Reason 26 (1994): 4–5.
Prado, C. G. Choosing to Die: Elective Death and Multiculturalism. Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Prentice, R. A.“The Case of the Irrational Auditor: A Behavioral Insight into Securities Fraud Litigation.”Northwestern University Law Review 95 (2000): 133–219.
Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press, 1971.
Raz, J.The Morality of Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Raz, J.Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press, 1999.
Reich, R.“How and Why to Support Common Schooling and Educational Choice at the Same Time.”Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (2007): 709–725.
Research for Action. “Freshman Year Policy Brief,” 2010. .
Reynolds, D. “Forced to Be Fit at Work?: With Health Care Costs Soaring, Some Employers Are Giving an Ultimatum: Shape up or Pay Up,” February 11, 2009. .
Richardson, H. S.“The Stupidity of the Cost–Benefit Standard.”The Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000): 971–1003.
Robbins, L. “Lost in the School Choice Maze.” The New York Times, May 6, 2011. .
Rosen, A. D. Kant’s Theory of Justice. Cornell University Press, 1993.
Rosenfeld, S. B.“Mandatory Pro Bono: Historical and Constitutional Perspectives.”Cardozo Law Review 2 (1981): 255–297.
Rothbard, M. N.Man, Economy, and State: A Treatise on Economic Principles. New York: Van Nostrand, 1962.
Sagoff, M.“At the Shrine of Our Lady of Fatima or Why Political Questions Are Not All Economic.”Arizona Law Review 23 (1981): 1283–1298.
Sagoff, M.“Values and Preferences.”Ethics 96 (1986): 301–316.
Salvat, C. “Is Libertarian Paternalism an Oxymoron? A Comment on Sunstein and Thaler.”HAL Working Papers Series, no. hal-00336528, version 1 (2008).
Satz, D.“Equality, Adequacy, and Education for Citizenship.”Ethics 117 (2007): 623–648.
Scanlon, T. M. What We Owe to Each Other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999.
Schapiro, T.“What Is a Child?”Ethics 109 (1999): 715–738.
Schauer, F.“Is There a Psychology of Judging?” In Klein, D. B. and Mitchell, G., eds., The Psychology of Judicial Decision Making. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010, 103–120.
Schlozman, K. L., and Tierney, J. T.. Organized Interests and American Democracy. New York: Harper & Row, 1986.
Schmidtz, D.“A Place for Cost–Benefit Analysis.”Noûs 35 (2001): 148–171.
Schneider, M., Teske, P., and Marschall, M.. Choosing Schools: Consumer Choice and the Quality of American Schools. Princeton University Press, 2002.
Schneider, M., Teske, P., Roch, C., and Marschall, M.. “Networks to Nowhere: Segregation and Stratification in Networks of Information About Schools.”American Journal of Political Science 41 (1997): 1201–1223.
Schwartz, B., Ward, A., Monterosso, J., Lyubomirsky, S., White, K., and Lehman, D. R.. “Maximizing Versus Satisficing: Happiness Is a Matter of Choice.”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83 (2002): 1178–1197.
Scoccia, D.“Paternalism and Respect for Autonomy.”Ethics 100 (1990): 318–334.
Scoccia, D.“In Defense of Hard Paternalism.”Law and Philosophy 27 (2008): 351–381.
Sen, A. K.“Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 6 (1977): 317–344.
Shanteau, J.“Competence in Experts: The Role of Task Characteristics.”Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 53 (1992): 252–266.
Shanteau, J.“Expert Judgment and Financial Decision Making.” In Green, B., ed., Risky Business: Risk Behavior and Risk Management. Stockholm University, 1995, 203–215.
Shanteau, J.“Psychological Characteristics and Strategies of Expert Decision Makers.”Acta Psychologica 68 (1988): 203–215.
Shapiro, D. L.“Courts, Legislatures, and Paternalism.”Virginia Law Review 74 (1988): 519–575.
Shiffrin, S. V.“Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 29 (2000): 205–250.
Shin, J., and Ariely, D.. “Keeping Doors Open: The Effect of Unavailability on Incentives to Keep Options Viable.”Management Science 50 (2004): 575–586.
Siegel, K.“Psychosocial Aspects of Rational Suicide.”American Journal of Psychotherapy 40 (1986): 405–418.
Simmons, A. J.“Fair Play and Political Obligation: Twenty Years Later.” In Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations. Cambridge University Press, 2000, 27–42.
Simmons, A. J.“The Principle of Fair Play.” In Moral Principles and Political Obligations. Princeton University Press, 1979, 101–142.
Slovic, P.“Perception of Risk.”Science 236 (1987): 280–285.
Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B., and Lichtenstein, S.. “Characterizing Perceived Risk.” In Kates, R. W., Hohenemser, C., and Kasperson, J. X., eds., Perilous Progress: Managing the Hazards of Technology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1985, 91–125.
Snyder, C. R., and Lopez, S. J.. Positive Psychology: The Scientific and Practical Explorations of Human Strengths. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2006.
Stewart, T., Wolf, P., Cornman, S. Q., McKenzie-Thompson, K., and Butcher, J.. Family Reflections on the District of Columbia Opportunity Scholarship Program: Final Summary Report. University of Arkansas School Choice Demonstration Project, 2009.
Stiglitz, J. E., Sen, A., and Fitoussi, J. P.. Report by the Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress. The Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress, 2009.
Sullum, J.“Freedom Riders: How Motorcyclists Won the Right to Feel the Wind in Their Hair – and Why Drivers Still Have to Buckle Up.”Reason 37 (2005): 40–46.
Sunstein, C. R.“Cognition and Cost–Benefit Analysis.”The Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000): 1059–1103.
Sunstein, C. R.“The Laws of Fear.”Harvard Law Review 115 (2002): 1119–1168.
Sunstein, C. R.“Legal Interference with Private Preferences.”University of Chicago Law Review 53 (1986): 1129–1184.
Sunstein, C. R.The Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary Principle. Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Sunstein, C. R., and Thaler, R. H.. “Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron.”University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 1159–1202.
Sunstein, C. R., and Ullmann-Margalit, E.. “Second-Order Decisions.”Ethics 110 (1999): 5–31.
Sussman, D.“What’s Wrong with Torture?”Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005): 1–33.
Swift, A.How Not to Be a Hypocrite: School Choice for the Morally Perplexed Parent. London: Routledge, 2003.
Talbott, W. J. Human Rights and Human Well-Being. Oxford University Press, 2010.
Taylor, J. S.“Introduction.” In Taylor, J. S., ed., Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 2005, 1–29.
Teno, J. M., Hakim, R. B., Knaus, W. A., Wenger, N. S., Phillips, R. S., Wu, A. W., Layde, P., Connors, A. F., Dawson, N. V., and Lynn, J.. “Preferences for Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation: Physician–Patient Agreement and Hospital Resource Use.”Journal of General Internal Medicine 10 (1995): 179–186.
Tetlock, P. E.“Thinking the Unthinkable: Sacred Values and Taboo Cognitions.”Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (2003): 320–324.
Thaler, R. H., and Sunstein, C. R.. “Libertarian Paternalism.”The American Economic Review 93 (2003): 175–179.
Thaler, R. H., and Sunstein, C. R.. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. Yale University Press, 2008.
Thaler, R. H., Sunstein, C. R., and Balz, J.. “Choice Architecture.” SSRN Working Paper Series (2010). .
Trout, J. D.The Empathy Gap: Building Bridges to the Good Life and the Good Society. New York: Viking Adult, 2009.
Trout, J. D.“Paternalism and Cognitive Bias.”Law and Philosophy 24 (2005): 393–434.
US Census Bureau. “State & County QuickFacts: Philadelphia County, Pennsylvania,” January 31, 2012. .
Valdman, M.“The Deep Problem with Voluntaristic Theories of Political Obligation.”American Philosophical Quarterly 47 (2010): 267–278.
VanDeVeer, D. Paternalistic Intervention: The Moral Bounds of Benevolence. Princeton University Press, 1986.
Viteritti, J. P.Choosing Equality: School Choice, the Constitution, and Civil Society. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, 1999.
Waldron, J.“Autonomy and Perfectionism in Raz’s Morality of Freedom.”Southern California Law Review 62 (1988): 1097–1152.
Wall, S. Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint. Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Wall, S. “Self-Ownership and Paternalism.”Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (2009): 399–417.
Wellman, C. H.“Samaritanism and the Duty to Obey the Law.” In Wellman, C. H. and Simmons, A. J., eds., Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?Cambridge University Press, 2005, 1–92.
Wellman, C. H., and Simmons, A. J., eds. Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Werth, J. L.Rational Suicide?: Implications for Mental Health Professionals. Boca Raton, FL: Taylor & Francis, 1996.
Werth, J. L., and Cobia, D. C.. “Empirically Based Criteria for Rational Suicide: A Survey of Psychotherapists.”Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 25 (1995): 231–240.
Westerman, D. A.“Expert and Novice Teacher Decision Making.”Journal of Teacher Education 42 (1991): 292–305.
White, M. D.“Behavioral Law and Economics: The Assault on Consent, Will, and Dignity.” In Gaus, G., Favor, C., and Lamont, J., eds., Essays on Philosophy, Politics & Economics: Integration & Common Research Projects. Stanford University Press, 2010, 201–223.
Whitman, G., and Rizzo, M. J.. “Paternalist Slopes.”New York University Journal of Law and Liberty 2 (2007): 411–443.
Wikler, D.“Paternalism and the Mildly Retarded.”Philosophy & Public Affairs 8 (1979): 377–392.
Wilson, T. D., and Gilbert, D. T.. “Affective Forecasting.”Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 35 (2003): 345–411.
Wise, T. A. “Small-Scale Farmers and Development: Assume a Different Economic Model.” Triple Crisis: Global Perspectives on Finance, Development, and Environment, September 27, 2010. .
Wolf, P., Eissa, N., and Babette, G.. “Who Chooses, Who Uses? Initial Evidence from the D.C. Opportunity Scholarship Program.” Education Working Paper Archive (July 6, 2006). .
Wonnell, C. T.“The Contractual Disempowerment of Employees.”Stanford Law Review 46 (1993): 87–145.
Wood, B. D., and Waterman, R. W.. Bureaucratic Dynamics: The Role of Bureaucracy in a Democracy. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1994.
Wright, G., Bolger, F., and Rowe, G.. “An Empirical Test of the Relative Validity of Expert and Lay Judgments of Risk.”Risk Analysis 22 (2002): 1107–1122.
Wright, W. F.“Audit Judgment Consensus and Experience.” In Ferris, K. R., ed., Behavioral Accounting Research: A Critical Analysis. Post Falls, ID: Century, 1988, 305–328.
Zaleskiewicz, T.“Financial Forecasts During the Crisis: Were Experts More Accurate Than Laypeople?”Journal of Economic Psychology 32 (2011): 384–390.
Zamir, E.“The Efficiency of Paternalism.”Virginia Law Review 84 (1998): 229–286.
Zweig, A., ed. Kant: Philosophical Correspondence, 1759–1799. University of Chicago Press, 1967.

Metrics

Altmetric attention score

Full text views

Total number of HTML views: 0
Total number of PDF views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

Book summary page views

Total views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.