As Craig Steven Titus notes, in comparison with the social sciences approach, this resilient attitude is not a simple “coping” with hardship. In the face of difficulties, some people are able to survive while others fall. Understanding these phenomena requires placing them within the framework of the meaning of moral life (Oviedo,
2019; Titus,
2006). The point is to look at the principles of human development and flourishing thanks to which we have a better understanding of the necessity of virtues. At the same time, it is a challenge for our theological considerations on the nature of God and for our understanding of events or situations perceived as difficult that are permitted by God. Aquinas correlates this with God’s goodness, which reaches even demons and the temptations or trials to which they subject humans:
…man’s welfare is disposed by Divine providence in two ways: first of all, directly, when a man is brought unto good and withheld from evil; and this is fittingly done through the good angels. In another way, indirectly, as when anyone assailed is exercised by fighting against opposition. It was fitting for this procuring of man’s welfare to be brought about through the wicked spirits, lest they should cease to be of service in the natural order (Aquinas,
2014, I, q. 64, a. 4 resp.).
This statement of Aquinas offers a framework for perceiving difficulties and recognizing their role in strengthening the human being in good (which, by the way, is the essence of “salvation”:
conservari in bono). Even mistakes made on this journey are useful, and we should be grateful to those who commit them (Roszak,
2017, p. 32). In this paper, however, we are more interested in resilience as a person’s attitude toward difficulties or, in other words, in the vision of Christian life rather than in God’s perspective.
In the Face of Difficulties: Are Trials and Temptations an Opportunity for Growth?
The terminology that Aquinas uses with reference to difficulties, from
tribulatio to
adversitas,
difficultas and
infirmitas to
affligio, presents us with his anthropological vision: a vision in which, besides man’s good and natural desires, there is also a reality that distracts man from good. Despite its potential dangers, Aquinas ultimately perceives it in a positive light because it indirectly helps in the strengthening of a human being (Boyle,
2014).
The significance of these adversities is presented profoundly in his commentary on the words “My grace is sufficient for you, for My strength is made perfect in weakness” from 2 Corinthians 12:9 (Vlg: virtus in infirmitate perficitur). Aquinas observes that weaknesses can contribute to strength in two ways: materialiter, when they provide the material for an act of fortitude, but also ocasionaliter, when they stimulate a concern for good. Trials show a human being’s vulnerability, provoking a response in the form of humility but also affirming the human integrity and capacity to develop oneself through the habitus. On account of their orientation toward exercising human abilities and making people stronger, Aquinas affirms that weaknesses are in some sense useful, which is why God permits them—because in this manner, good can be developed. This is also why they are ordained to the good (ordinaverat hoc ad bonum). Interestingly, to support his view, Aquinas offers two examples from ancient military practice and politics: the fact that Scipio Africanus did not destroy Carthage completely and that in the case of the conquest of the Promised Land, God permitted peoples to live there even though He knew that they would fight against Israel later.
Thomas interprets the Pauline idea as an indication of where the source of strength lies and uses it to show that we need grace to gain our full strength. From this perspective, it becomes clear why St. Paul prayed and gave thanks for weaknesses: not for their own sake but for the reason that the power of Christ can appear through them. This is a paradox which Aquinas summarizes using the phrase “fire grows in water” (Aquinas,
2012b, 2 Corinthians, c. 12, l. 3).
Difficult experiences and dangers marked by risks, however, have a positive effect, as evidenced by the very etymology of the word “experience,” which “finds its roots in the practical knowledge, skill or competence (
peritia) that we draw from a trial or danger (
periculum) once overcome” (Titus,
2006, p. 209). Not all experiences will result in such competence, however, because they require special help in order to become integrated instead of simply becoming a sequence of individual impressions.
Indeed, the virtue of fortitude is forged in the face of dangers and can be manifested in different ways. As he addresses the question of the achievement of the difficult good (
bonum arduum), Thomas points to two virtues that prepare the human mind to meet the dangers:
magnanimitas (or
fiducia) and
magnificentia. Their fundamental role is to show how a person can rebuild his or her life after an experience of falling and how risks can be taken when it comes to the greater good. They are responsible for the first aspect of fortitude, which Aquinas refers to as
aggredi (initiative and attack), whereas the second one,
sustinere (resistance and endurance), is shaped by
patientia and
perseverantia (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 128, a. 1 resp.). Thanks to them, a balance is achieved in human life through which one can strive for good in an orderly manner, according to reason and eternal law. The attainment of these virtues—which are integral parts of fortitude—is crucial to moral life because they prepare a person for perfect action (Huzarek,
2021; Irwin,
2021). However, humans also encounter pitfalls in the form of the weakness of
pusillanimitas, which manifests itself in uncertainty and timidity (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 133, a. 1 resp.). Nevertheless, the characteristic of
arduum as the object of the virtue of fortitude
, as noted by Gauthier and quoted by Titus (
2006, p. 289), concern greatness or excellence rather than difficulty: in the Thomistic vocabulary, it is a synonym of
magnum,
altum,
elevatum or
excellens.
In a situation (very common in pastoral care) where something interferes with the achievement of the desired good, there are two possible ways of helping: explanation of the difficulties or survival among them. In these challenging moments, Aquinas recommends what he calls
firmitas animi, which belongs to the virtue of fortitude (Aquinas,
2014, I-II, q. 65, a. 1 resp.) and can be observed in many aspects of Christian life, such as pilgrimage (Seryczyńska & Duda,
2021). Therefore, he describes it as “strength of mind in bearing with passing trials” (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 58, a. 8 ad 2)
. This cardinal virtue allows man not to succumb to the fear that arises when the adversities are great: it makes man’s will resistant and rooted in the good of reason (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 123, a. 4 resp.).
From the theological perspective, temporal adversities (such as
poenae) are not completely removed by the Passion of Christ or reduced in their intensity because as long as we are on our way to beatitude (
in statu viae), they often have a stimulating effect on human life, leading to the most important “growth of love”: they may turn out to be a remedy for the worst diseases of the human spirit (Aquinas,
2012a,
c. 12, l. 3). When we reach heaven, however, all of them will be removed by the application of the power of Christ’s Passion.
Flourishing and Resilience
For Thomas Aquinas, moral life is not an automatic process of ethical judgment in which we rely on some external principles, since such an approach would reduce moral theology to simply knowing what is allowed and what is not. How can one react when weakness arises? Many people see living a moral life as not backing away an inch, as being rigid, as not crossing a boundary. However, in human moral action, Thomas sees an orientation toward flourishing which is assisted by virtues, and from the perspective of “happiness,” he builds a vision of Christian morality. This is the first goal of moral action: to achieve
beatitudo, which has both passive and active aspects (Hankey,
2018). Furthermore, this is the correct perspective for resilience: it is a way to achieve happiness that consists in reaching fulfilment in the intellectual and volitional areas. In other words, it is the blossoming of a human being who is anticipating, through faith, eternal happiness: participation in the nature of God.
In light of all these observations, Christian moral life does not consist in eliminating passions but rather in properly ordering them toward a goal according to reason. In Thomistic anthropology, human emotions such as fear are not to be denied or treated as evil; on the contrary, emotions must be used in a creative and consistent way. Fear is not bad in itself (in fact, it has two faces like a coin: a filial one and an enslaving one) and may have a mobilizing rather than paralyzing effect under certain circumstances. Therefore, in an emotional state, one must not focus solely on what is difficult and must instead grasp one’s tendencies to love, both in concupiscible passions (regarding what is good and evil in and of itself) and in irascible ones (where the criterion is difficulty).
This is why Titus (
2006) claims that the virtue of fortitude seems to correspond to what is nowadays referred to as resilience. Although there is no strictly equivalent term for resilience in Aquinas’s vocabulary, fortitude—mainly in the sense of moral strength in its rational, involuntary and affective manifestations—is what clearly corresponds to resilience as a means of overcoming difficulty. Moreover, every virtue is resilient in some sense because in each virtue, it is necessary to find an optimum, a golden mean between extremes, even if this is not a mathematical middle point but a right measure. In Aquinas’s philosophy, feelings are supposed to be managed in a political rather than despotic manner: they should be moved by reason, not by force.
The object of fortitude is what takes place
in sustinendis et repellendis (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 123, a. 2 resp.), and it is oriented toward
ad resistendum impugnationibus (Aquinas,
2014, II-II, q. 123, a. 2 ad 2). Passions can be harnessed to confront and overcome difficulties, although Thomas is aware of how passions affect reason and imagination, reducing attention and concentration on achieving goals. Fear can also contribute to reduced motivation by discouraging a person from acting. At the same time, however, fear can be conducive to action, for “if the fear be moderate, without much disturbance of the reason, it conduces to working well, in so far as it causes a certain solicitude, and makes a man take counsel and work with greater attention” (Aquinas,
2014, I-II, q. 44, a. 4 ad 3). A servant’s fear, to quote Aquinas’s example, can contribute to his greater dedication or attention to work. Such fear can be positive in its impact because it stimulates attention and provokes profound reflection and carefulness.
Furthermore, an aspect which should be important to pastoral theology is that fortitude consists in a certain integration between perception, emotion, reason and will. For Thomas, there is no static perfection in his ethics of virtues. Instead, since virtues are interrelated in a variety of ways (ranging from some virtues being constituents of others to the mutual influence of various virtues due to a
nexus virtutum), understanding the mechanism of resilience requires taking into account and identifying the beneficial influence of many virtues. Fortitude gives rise to an emotional calm thanks to which attachments are created, and these in turn provide security. Resilience does not indicate pre-existing solutions, instead adapting the means to the situation: being resilient does not mean systematically or continuously evading difficulties or avoiding any spiritual fights but rather confronting evil or adversity when appropriate (Huetter,
2014). In this context, an indication of “when” to act can be achieved thanks to the
recta ratio.