Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Infectious Diseases and Therapy 1/2021

Open Access 10.11.2020 | Commentary

Pediatric Vaccines and Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds: How Much is Too Much to Pay for Prevention?

verfasst von: Jordan Amdahl, Derek Weycker, Ray Farkouh, Liping Huang, Caitlin Eichten, Gerry Oster

Erschienen in: Infectious Diseases and Therapy | Ausgabe 1/2021

Abstract

Cost-effectiveness evaluations play an important role in recommendations for use of pediatric vaccines that are set forth by the US Advisory Committee on Immunization Practices (ACIP). The fact that these evaluations are undertaken and accorded weight suggests that a critical value for designating pediatric vaccines as cost-effective (or not) must exist. For recommended pediatric vaccines, however, reported incremental cost-effectiveness ratios (ICERs) have varied greatly, and there does not appear to be an explicit threshold used by the ACIP to define how much is too much to pay for the prevention of communicable diseases in children. Further complicating this issue is the fact that conventional ICER thresholds—expressed in terms of cost per quality-adjusted life-year (QALY) gained—accord value only to length and quality of life and may not reflect our preferences as individuals or a society. For example, risk, an important attribute of many healthcare decisions, is ignored by the QALY model, as is the distribution of health benefits across different members of society. Are we indeed indifferent about risk and do we really believe that the value of disease prevention in children should be measured by the same “yardstick” as that for older adults? Accordingly, do we really believe that “a QALY is a QALY”? These issues, which are reviewed and discussed in this article, are more than just of theoretical interest; the answers impact how public health policy is determined, which impacts the lives and well-being of entire populations as well as the budgets of payers.
Key Summary Points
While the cost-per-QALY framework is unquestionably a useful one in framing and addressing questions of value for money, this metric may not reflect our preferences (e.g., in terms of risk aversion or distribution of health outcomes) as individuals or a society.
Such limitations warrant a serious reexamination of how cost-effectiveness thresholds should be applied in healthcare decisions.
This is especially important when these decisions concern the use of pediatric vaccines against rare and unpredictable diseases.

Digital Features

This article is published with digital features, including a summary slide, to facilitate understanding of the article. To view digital features for this article go to https://​doi.​org/​10.​6084/​m9.​figshare.​13135730.

Introduction

Over the last few decades, economic evaluations have come to play an increasingly important—and often prominent—role in decision making regarding the adoption and use of new medical technologies. In countries such as England, Australia, and Canada, estimates of cost-effectiveness are a key input into decisions regarding the allocation of public sector healthcare resources [13]. In the US, however, notwithstanding the fact that health economists, decision scientists, and health services researchers have long played an important role in the development, refinement, and practical application of methods of economic evaluation in medicine, explicit use of cost-effectiveness criteria in healthcare decision making remains the exception rather than the rule. Indeed, the Center for Medicare and Medicaid Services (CMS), which is the primary insurer for approximately 50 million Medicare beneficiaries in the US, is explicitly barred from considering questions of cost-effectiveness in its coverage decisions; CMS is supposed to make such decisions based simply on whether treatments are “reasonable and necessary,” without consideration of whether they provide value for money [4].
The Advisory Committee on Immunization Practices (ACIP) of the US Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) represents a notable exception to the generally limited use of economic evaluations and cost-effectiveness criteria in healthcare decision making in the US. The Committee, which consists of a group of medical and public health experts, advises the CDC about how vaccines should be used to control preventable diseases in the US [5]. The CDC, in turn, sets the childhood and adult immunization schedule based on the Committee’s recommendations. Vaccines that are part of the childhood schedule are covered under the Vaccines for Children (VFC) program, which provides vaccines free of charge to children who otherwise might not be immunized because of economic circumstances as well as applicable health plans under the Affordable Care Act [6]. Although the recommendations of the ACIP do not carry legal mandates, they are used by both the federal government and private insurers to determine vaccine coverage and reimbursement [7].
While the ACIP typically considers various factors in its deliberations concerning the use of new vaccines as well as expanded indications for existing ones, such as the incidence and severity of the disease in question, and the safety, efficacy, and effectiveness of the vaccine under consideration, cost-effectiveness—i.e., if a vaccination program is a reasonable and efficient allocation of resources—is one of the criteria that the Committee explicitly considers [8]. Over the past decade, the ACIP has cited findings of favorable cost-effectiveness in its support of the use of a number of vaccines, including the human papillomavirus vaccine (HPV) in 12-year-old girls ($3000–$45,000 per quality-adjusted life-year [QALY] gained) [9]; the 13-valent pneumococcal conjugate vaccine (PCV-13) in infants and children aged < 6 years (cost-saving versus the 7-valent vaccine [PCV-7] [10] and $20,200 per QALY gained as a single supplemental dose in selected patients) [10]; influenza vaccine among persons aged 50–64 years and ≥ 65 years ($28,000 and $980 per QALY gained, respectively) [11]; and the recombinant zoster vaccine (RZV) among immunocompetent adults aged ≥ 50 years ($31,000 per QALY gained) [12]. However, it is also true that the ACIP has recommended use of vaccines in the absence of a favorable cost-effectiveness ratio, because either a ratio had not been reported or the estimated ratio was found to be unfavorable.
One of the more recent economic evaluations considered by the ACIP concerned the use of a quadrivalent vaccine against invasive meningococcal disease (IMD), an acute infection of the bloodstream and the membranes surrounding the central nervous system. The disease is caused by the bacterium Neisseria meningitidis (or meningococcus), which is a leading cause of bacterial meningitis and sepsis in the US today [1315]. The rate of fatality in IMD is approximately 10%, even with appropriate treatment, and approximately 30% of survivors experience permanent sequelae, including neurologic damage, hearing loss, renal failure, paralysis, and amputation [16]. While N. meningitidis remains susceptible to many commonly used antibiotics, treatment is often initiated too late to significantly alter the course of the disease and to prevent complications and death; prevention is therefore a much better clinical strategy than treatment [13, 14].
Almost all cases of IMD in the US are caused by strains from one of four N. meningitidis serogroups (B, C, Y, and W) or non-groupable strains, although the breakdown of cases by serogroup varies by age [17]. In 2005, the first quadrivalent vaccine that was effective against serogroups A, C, W, and Y (MenACWY) was licensed for use among persons aged 11–55 years. In that same year, in response to rising disease incidence (especially among persons aged ≥ 11 years) and disease severity and based—at least in part—on the results of cost-effectiveness analyses, the ACIP recommended routine vaccination with one dose of MenACWY for persons aged 11–12 years, persons entering high school if not previously vaccinated with MenACWY, and other persons at increased risk of meningococcal disease, including college freshmen living in dormitories [1719].
In recommending the use of MenACWY in adolescents, the ACIP cited a cost-effectiveness ratio of $212,000 per QALY gained [17]. While there is no explicit cost-effectiveness threshold that the ACIP uses to define how much is too much to pay for prevention of communicable diseases, the estimated ratio for MenACWY in adolescents is substantially higher than that of other vaccines also recommended by the ACIP in recent years. The estimated cost-effectiveness ratio for MenACWY also substantially exceeds: (1) the threshold of $50,000 per QALY gained that frequently has been used in the US to identify interventions that provide “value for money,” notwithstanding the fact that this figure is > 30 years old [20, 21]; (2) the threshold of $100,000 per QALY gained, which has been suggested as a more appropriate figure to use in the US today [22]; and (3) the World Health Organization’s (WHO) suggested rule of thumb of three times the per-capita GDP [20], which would yield a current threshold for the US of almost $160,000 per QALY gained. Notably, in June 2015, the ACIP provided guidance that adolescents and young adults aged 16–23 years may be immunized with MenB vaccine to provide short-term protection against most strains of serogroup B meningococcal disease and reported estimates of cost per QALY gained ranging from $3.7 to $9.4 million [23]. While the ACIP did not render a routine recommendation for use of MenB vaccine in this population, the reasons cited included low disease prevalence and lack of important requisite data; an unfavorable cost-effectiveness profile was not mentioned.
This question about the right value to use as a cost-effectiveness threshold is especially interesting in the case of pediatric vaccines. If a threshold did not exist above which ACIP would deem a particular vaccine too expensive to use in relation to the clinical benefits it would confer, then economic evaluations of vaccines would be a largely academic exercise. The fact that these evaluations are undertaken and accorded weight in the ACIP’s deliberations suggests—in principle, at least—that such a critical value indeed must exist. A central question, therefore, particularly from a societal perspective, is how much is too much to pay for a pediatric vaccine? This issue is of more than just theoretical interest, since the answers impact how public health policy is determined, which, in turn, impacts the lives and well-being of entire populations as well as the budgets of payers. This article is based on previously conducted studies and does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Some Reflections on the QALY Framework

In numerous respects, the pace of advancement in medical science has been dizzying in recent years and promises only to increase with expanding knowledge about the biologic basis of disease and our growing ability to target specific mechanisms. Our desire to reap the benefits that modern medicine increasingly can confer undoubtedly will increase apace. As it does, it will inevitably continue to bump up against the limits of affordability and cause a central question to be posed again and again: How much of our economic resources—either as individual consumers or as a nation as a whole—do we want to devote to medical care? It is almost inevitable that some medical interventions will be seen as providing good “value for money,” and others will be seen as being priced too high relative to the clinical benefits they confer. A fundamental problem of resource allocation in medicine is to figure out how to distinguish between the two.
Cost-effectiveness analysis is an exceedingly attractive tool for dealing with such problems. In a cost-effectiveness analysis, clinical outcomes and economic costs are compared under two alternative scenarios: one that assumes that an intervention of interest would be used in a particular fashion and another that assumes that it would not be used in the contemplated manner. An incremental cost-effectiveness ratio (ICER) is then obtained by dividing the estimated difference in costs between the two scenarios by the corresponding expected difference in health outcomes. The ICER represents the estimated “bang for the buck”—or, more accurately, the “bucks for the bang”—to move from the less effective treatment to the one that is more effective. All else equal, lower ICERs are preferable to higher ones, as they indicate that a given amount of health can be “purchased” at a lower price with one intervention versus the other. Healthcare decision makers thus can increase aggregate health benefits for any given level of expenditure by allocating resources to therapies with lower ICERs versus those with higher ones [24]. This criterion is sometimes referred to as economic efficiency.
Techniques of cost-effectiveness analysis have been applied to a wide range of diseases and interventions—from asthma inhalers [25] to drugs to treat cancer [26]. Many areas of medicine have their own preferred measures of clinical benefit, making it challenging to compare economic value across a diverse range of diseases and therapies. In some settings, it may be useful to know how much it costs to “produce” an additional symptom-free day in patients with asthma, while in others it may be useful to know the cost of delaying disease progression by 1 month in patients with advanced cancer. Determining which of these two interventions provides better value for money, however, requires a yardstick capable of translating qualitatively different health benefits to an identical measurement scale. While some may cringe at the thought of having to decide between a new drug for patients with asthma versus another one for patients with advanced cancer, if we cannot agree that such decisions inevitably must be made, then we are effectively conceding that no amount of money spent on healthcare could ever be too much, no matter the sacrifices that this might entail in other aspects of our lives. When framed in this fashion, we suspect that most people would concede that such comparisons are necessary.
One of the key milestones in the development and refinement of methods of cost-effectiveness analysis was the concept of the quality-adjusted life-year, or “QALY.” Over the past 2 decades, QALYs have emerged as the standard metric for measuring health outcomes in economic evaluations [27]. The QALY is a composite measure that takes into account both the length of a person’s life and its quality. QALYs often are calculated by segmenting the time that a person is alive into intervals that he or she spends in different health states. Each such health state is assigned a preference weight (or “utility value”) that reflects its desirability in relation to a state of “perfect health” (which is assigned a value of 1) and death (which is assigned a value of 0). QALYs are tallied by multiplying the time that patients spend in each health state by its corresponding utility value [28] and then summing these products. In this manner, QALYs facilitate comparisons of interventions across a wide range of conditions [29], effectively making the incomparable comparable.
While QALYs represented an important step in the development of methods of economic evaluation in medicine, in that they recognize that individuals and society value both length and quality of life, one must also consider how well the so-called QALY model truly reflects preferences from the individual and/or societal perspectives. While it may not be immediately apparent, if asked about how they think limited healthcare resources should be allocated, many people would express or reveal a preference for additional considerations or attributes. To the extent that these additional factors affect our choices in the real world, the QALY model may provide an incomplete picture of how we value different interventions.
For example, one important attribute of some decisions that is ignored by the QALY model is risk. While attitudes toward risk are complicated, context-dependent, and subject to cognitive bias [30], it is well established that people often are willing to pay a great deal of money to avoid it. Examples abound of people willingly spending large amounts of money to avoid financial risk, whether in the form of insurance premiums or acceptance of a reduced rate of return to ensure the safety of their investments. With a bit of introspection, this behavior can easily be confirmed (Example #1).
Example #1: Business Venture
Suppose you are offered an opportunity to invest your life savings—let’s assume $20,000–in a new business venture that would double your money within 1 year if it is successful, and you believe there is a four-in-five (80%) chance that it will succeed. However, you also think there is a 20% chance that the venture will fail, and if it does, you will not be able to recoup anything from your initial investment. Would you be willing to risk your life savings in this business?
The expected value of this “gamble” is $32,000 (i.e., [80% × $40,000] + [20% × $0]), and the bet therefore is one that it would be wise to take on (assuming that the investment did not involve your entire life savings and that you could repeat it many times). In reality, however, most people would be too worried about the possibility of losing their life savings to agree to participate in such a venture, preferring instead a safer investment vehicle that yielded a lower rate of return. This sort of behavior, termed “risk aversion” by economists, raises an important point about how people make decisions under conditions of uncertainty. When disaster is one possible outcome, people may willingly give up a great deal for safety.
Given that catastrophic outcomes are an unavoidable part of many healthcare decisions, one might surmise that risks and attitudes toward risk would be an important factor in any decision framework. However, in the standard QALY model and therefore in the standard cost-effectiveness analysis framework, risk is treated as an irrelevant consideration. The use of cost-effectiveness analysis based on the QALY model explicitly assumes that people are risk-neutral with respect to outcomes [31]. In other words, methods of cost-effectiveness analysis assume that for any given amount of QALYs, people are indifferent about risk.
However, there are a plethora of examples (one of which is summarized in Example #2) that demonstrate the importance of ensuring that widely shared attitudes toward risk are incorporated into decision making paradigms. While the core assumption of risk neutrality has long been identified as a proper target for criticism of standard methods of cost-effectiveness analysis [31], there has been relatively little discussion about how attitudes toward risk should be incorporated into healthcare decision making. Nonetheless, some key points may be identified. Cost-effectiveness analyses of decisions that involve risk—especially where some outcomes may be disastrous—cannot simply focus on the expected overall number of QALYs produced by different treatment strategies without giving consideration to the range of possible outcomes and their likelihoods. If risk aversion is widespread, then decision makers should give greater priority to strategies that involve the avoidance of catastrophic outcomes, such as life-threatening diseases that strike in childhood [32].
Example #2: Life-Threatening Condition
Consider, for example, that you are the parent of a 10-year-old child who has been diagnosed with a life-threatening heart condition. With medical therapy alone, she would be expected to live a reasonably normal life until the age of 58 years (i.e., an additional 48 years of life). However, a surgical procedure also could be performed that, if successful, could extend her life by an additional 12 years beyond that afforded by medical therapy (i.e., to age 70 years), but which also involves an operative mortality risk of 20%. Note that the expected number of life-years for these two choices is identical (i.e., [100% × 48 years] = [80% × 60 years] + [20% × 0 years]).
Standard methods of cost-effectiveness analysis, and the application thereof, assume that we would be indifferent between these two treatment strategies and therefore would value them similarly. However, we suspect that under these circumstances, most parents would not want their child to undergo surgery.
In addition to ignoring the element of risk, traditional methods of cost-effectiveness analysis also disregard how health benefits are distributed among different members of society and focus simply on the expected total number of QALYs gained across all persons who would be impacted in a relevant accounting or social unit [33]. No consideration is given to how those QALYs are distributed. In the parlance of health economics, “a QALY is a QALY;” to whom it belongs is irrelevant (Fig. 1).
But is it indeed the case that we do not care how health benefits are distributed? Consider, for a moment, two persons with terminal cancer—one, a 12-year-old boy; the other, a 75-year-old man. Suppose that, with optimal palliative and supportive care, each could experience one additional QALY than would otherwise be the case. If care could only be provided to one of these two patients, and the decision were yours, would you be able pick a patient, and if so, which one would you pick? Most people, we believe, would express a clear preference for treating the young boy. Yet again, such behavior would be inconsistent with the conceptual foundation and framework of cost-effectiveness analysis. If a QALY is a QALY, then it should not matter to us who gets them.
Why do we seem to care how QALYs are distributed? One possible explanation can be found in the principles of fairness and equity. In particular, it seems especially unjust that some of us get to live to a ripe old age, while others are robbed of the chance for a long life for inexplicable reasons. Most of us find these kinds of inequalities upsetting, and by treating the older man instead of the boy, we would be widening the gap in QALYs between them. Treating the boy instead of the older man, on the other hand, feels right to us because we would be closing the gap, if only slightly. Evidence for this attitude can be found in the everyday language of death. People seem to view death very differently depending on when in life it occurs. When a child dies, it is very commonly referred to as a tragedy, yet when a person dies in old age, we often readily comment that he or she had a “full life” (usually, irrespective of how they actually spent it and the enjoyment they derived from it). While such events are still unhappy, we acknowledge that death is inevitable, and there is solace to be found when it occurs at an advanced age and in a comfortable setting. These are not thoughts that typically come to mind when a child dies.
The so-called “fair-innings argument,” coined by the British economist Alan Williams, builds on this attitude by making the claim that we are all “entitled” to a certain normal span of life and state of well-being [34] and that an important goal of healthcare decisions should be to reduce inequalities in the distribution of lifetime health outcomes. To the extent that outcomes-based equity considerations are important to us, such as the “fair-innings argument,” decision makers would be wrong in focusing simply on the total number of QALYs produced by a particular intervention without regard to how the benefits are distributed. The distribution of health benefits associated with interventions must be considered, and there should be recognition that, in some instances and in particular circumstances, we would willingly trade economic efficiency for equity (i.e., we would accept a lower total amount of QALYs in return for a distribution of benefits that we thought was more equitable). The implication is that in some situations and circumstances, policy makers might willingly accept treatments that offer fewer QALYs (i.e., have higher cost-effectiveness ratios) if the distribution of benefits is deemed more equitable [34]. In the present context, the implication is that we might want to accord greater value, all else equal, to interventions that can prevent diseases that rob children of “innings” that we think should be their due.
We note that the objective of this review article is not to address limitations inherent in QALYs and their measurement—including ethical, methodologic, and contextual concerns (e.g., variability/validity of instruments, numeracy challenges), especially in pediatric populations—since doing so would take us beyond our intended scope [35]. However, it is important to note that to the extent some of these limitations (e.g., imperfect information on future interventions and the timing of these interventions that may impact health) may modify perspectives on risk taking and thus decision making at a given point in time, the QALY concept may be further challenged. We also note our review article does not address the other component of cost-effectiveness ratios and its associated limitations, namely costs.

So How Much is Too Much to Pay?

Ultimately, the application of cost-effectiveness thresholds comes down to how much we are willing to pay to achieve outcomes that we desire and/or reduce the likelihood of experiencing outcomes that we would rather avoid. Conventional cost-effectiveness thresholds, expressed in terms of a cost per QALY gained, accord value only to the length and quality of life, irrespective of risk or how benefits are distributed. As we have discussed in the preceding section, attitudes toward risk and how outcomes are distributed are often important considerations in decision making about healthcare. To the extent that these concerns and issues are real elements of social preference, we should observe that people are willing to pay a premium to avoid catastrophic health outcomes, especially in children. An obvious question is whether people in fact behave in this manner?
Many surveys have examined how the value we place on an intervention may depend on factors beyond its expected total health benefits. Some studies have examined these choices as a function of risk preference at an individual level and asked respondents whether they would accept a greater risk of early death to improve their life expectancy. Hellinger [36], for example, surveyed 50 employees of the US Department of Health and Human Services about whether they would prefer a life expectancy of 30 years or an 80% chance of a life expectancy of 40 years and a 20% chance of immediate death. If people were not risk-averse, they should prefer the latter choice, as it involves an expected gain of 2 years of life in comparison with the risk-free option (i.e., [80% × 40 years + 20% × 0 years] > 100% × 30 years). Hellinger reported, however, that respondents were almost unanimous (96%) in their preference for the choice that did not involve a risk of instant death. In a similar study, Eraker and Sox [37] surveyed 523 persons about whether they preferred treatments with certain or uncertain effects with the same expected number of life-years. They examined cases where the expected gain ranged from 1 to 3 life-years, and in each case, they found that a statistically significant proportion of respondents preferred the “sure thing.” If risk aversion is apparent even when questions are hypothetical and stakes are as small as the loss of a single year of life, it is not hard to imagine that it could play a much greater role when the choices are real, and the stakes are much higher.
Other surveys have adopted a more societal perspective and asked respondents to choose between healthcare programs targeted at different age groups. Johannesson and Johansson, for example, surveyed a random sample of 1000 persons in Sweden, aged 15 years or older, about whether they would prefer a hypothetical program that saves 100 lives among 50 year olds or one that saves 50 lives among 30 year olds [38]. The number of persons saved in the 50-year-old group was varied to determine the point at which respondents thought the two programs were of equal value. They then used general-population mortality rates and utility values to estimate the implied QALYs gained by each program. In doing so, they found that preferences expressed by survey respondents implied that a QALY gained for a person aged 30 years was “worth” 3.9 times that of a QALY gained for someone aged 50 years. They then repeated the survey using an older comparison group and reported that a QALY gained for a person aged 30 years was accorded a value 16 times greater than that of QALY gained for someone 70 years of age. Such extreme results are obviously difficult to reconcile with a model that assumes that a QALY is a QALY, regardless of whose it is, and one wonders whether the result might have been even more extreme if children rather than 30 year olds had been considered. A study by Mooney, Jan, and Wiseman asked respondents whether they would prefer a program that offered 1000 units of “health gain” to people aged 20–30 years or a similar program that offered the same benefit to persons aged 60–70 years [39]. While a plurality of respondents (45.9%) answered that these programs were equally valuable, far more respondents preferred the program for younger persons (39.9%) than the program for older persons (11.3%). While this result does not support widespread preference for the young, it does suggest that such preferences exist in the aggregate.
In addition to surveys that ask purely hypothetical questions, evidence of social preferences also may be found in real-life decisions that are made by patients, parents, and regulators on a daily basis. If a preference for risk aversion and equitable distribution of health outcomes is common, then we should expect to find examples of decision makers willingly spending large amounts of money to avoid even small risks of catastrophic outcomes or to achieve even modest health gains in children. A potent example of this may be found in the private banking of umbilical cord blood, which has shown promise in treating various diseases, including metabolic disorders, leukemia, and cerebral palsy [40]. The potential therapeutic value of cord blood has led to the creation of for-profit banks that offer to store cord blood collected at birth in case it is needed later in life. The likelihood that banked cord blood will actually be used, however, remains extremely low—reportedly, as low as 1 in every 250,000 “deposits” [41].
A cost-effectiveness analysis found that, even with extremely generous assumptions, the cost-effectiveness of banking cord blood was well in excess of $1,000,000 per life year gained [40]. Yet its high price has not stopped parents from banking the cord blood of their children; currently, an estimated 1.7 million cord blood samples are being held in private storage banks [42]. The fact that so many parents believe that the banking of umbilical cord blood offers reasonable value for money suggests that there is considerable demand for healthcare interventions that hold out the promise of reducing even small risks of catastrophic outcomes in children, even if their cost-effectiveness ratios vastly exceed any current benchmark of how value should be assessed in healthcare. Other examples in which similar decisions have been made include child safety regulations (Example #3) and homeland security (Example #4).
Example #3: Child Safety Regulation
The Consumer Product Safety Commission is responsible for federal regulation involving the safety of children’s clothing. Current regulatory standards for children’s sleepwear, sizes 7–14, require that it be flame-resistant and that it self-extinguish if lit by an open flame. Based on the results of an analysis of flammability standards [43], the cost-effectiveness of this rule was estimated to be $160,000 per life-year gained in 1993 dollars [44]. Updated to 2019 prices, this figure would be approximately $283,000 per life-year gained—again, well above just about any currently accepted cost-effectiveness threshold. Yet, to the best of our knowledge, a hue and cry has not been heard for repeal of this regulatory standard.
To provide another example, the safety of school buses in the US is regulated by the National Highway Traffic Safety Administration. Current regulations require that all new school buses be constructed with seat backs at least 24 inches high and with extendable signal arms that can be deployed to alert nearby drivers to the existence of pedestrians in the vicinity of the bus. According to the National Resource Council [45], the cost-effectiveness of 24-inch seat backs was $150,000 per life-year gained in 1993 dollars ($265,000 in 2019 dollars); the cost-effectiveness of signal arms was $430,000 per life-year gained in 1993 dollars ($761,000 in 2019 dollars) [44]. While these estimates are provided in terms of costs per life-year rather than per QALY gained, it remains unlikely that these interventions would be cost-effective by any conventional standard.
Example #4: Homeland Security
On a larger scale, societal attitudes toward risky life-and-death choices are also exemplified in the US by decisions involving homeland security. Thankfully, terrorist attacks on US soil are few and far between. When they do occur, however, their consequences can be devastating and scarring. Not surprisingly, public spending on homeland security has increased massively since the September 11th attacks [51]. Stewart, Ellinwood, and Mueller used this policy shift as a case study in risk aversion [52]. They reported that the added spending on homeland security probably would save many more lives if the funds were directed elsewhere. Even tornado shelters, they reported, which have been estimated to cost $6,000,000 per additional life saved, would be a better investment. Based on this information, the authors concluded that spending on homeland security was a classic illustration of the value we often place on risk aversion.
 

Summary

A large portion of healthcare spending goes toward extending and improving life among older adults during their final years [46, 47]. Vaccines are our first line of defense against a number of devastating diseases, but represent a relatively small portion of preventive healthcare expenditure [48]. Vaccine-preventable diseases in children can result in unnecessary morbidity and mortality, begging the question whether we really believe that the value of preventing these diseases should be measured by the same cost-per-QALY “yardstick” as adding another year of life to someone who already has many under his or her belt. Do we really believe that “a QALY is a QALY,” and are we indeed indifferent about risk? If not, then the yardstick that is commonly used in cost-effectiveness analysis may not be measuring what we sometimes think it is, and reliance upon it may yield outcomes that are inconsistent with our preferences.
With cost-effectiveness an explicit factor in ACIP’s Evidence to Recommendation framework [8], successful vaccine development requires not only evidence of safety and efficacy but also the foresight to predict trends in disease incidence many years into the future. In the case of IMD, the annual incidence rate has declined precipitously over the last 2 decades (from about 0.5 to 1.1 cases per 100,000 persons prior to 2000 to 0.1 cases per 100,000 in 2018) [49], and many have struggled with how to appropriately estimate the value of preventing a catastrophic disease that is rare but variable in its occurrence, subject to fluctuations over time and spontaneous outbreaks [50]. Unpredictable trends in disease incidence can yield important changes in the cost-effectiveness profile of a vaccine candidate from the time antigens are identified to when it is later appraised by regulatory agencies and reimbursement officials. Given the challenges of vaccine development and the consequences of incorrect decision making, it would be of paramount importance to ensure that cost-effectiveness thresholds that are applied to vaccines accurately reflect societal preferences.
We therefore believe that caution should be exercised when making use of conventional cost-effectiveness thresholds in deliberations concerning the use of vaccines against rare and unpredictable diseases. While the cost-per-QALY framework is unquestionably a useful one in framing problems of value for money, there are many potential sources of value that this metric does not consider. We note that while our review focused on the US and ACIP, the issues and challenges discussed in this review article apply to other countries around the world, notwithstanding differences in approaches to healthcare decision-making. Accordingly, we encourage similar reviews focusing on these alternative (i.e., ex-US) settings.
As we have shown, societal preferences for risk avoidance and more equitable distributions of health outcomes may affect how healthcare decisions are made in practice. While available evidence is more suggestive than definitive, we believe that it is sufficient to warrant a serious re-examination of how cost-effectiveness thresholds, either implicit or explicit, should be applied when decisions involve the prevention of devastating diseases in children and adolescents, such as IMD. Do we really know how much is too much to pay in these instances? At this point in time, unfortunately, the answer is probably “no.”

Acknowledgements

Funding

This study was sponsored by Pfizer Inc., who also funded the journal’s Rapid Service Fees.

Authorship

All named authors meet the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors (ICMJE) criteria for authorship for this article, take responsibility for the integrity of the work as a whole, and have given their approval for this version to be published.

Authorship Contributions

All authors contributed to literature reviews, manuscript writing, and reviewing.

Disclosures

Jordan Amdahl, Derek Weycker, Caitlin Eichten, and Gerry Oster are employees of Policy Analysis Inc., and were paid consultants to Pfizer in connection with the development of this manuscript. Liping Huang and Ray Farkouh are employees of Pfizer Inc.

Compliance with Ethics Guidelines

This article is based on previously conducted studies and does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License, which permits any non-commercial use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by-nc/​4.​0/​.
Literatur
5.
Zurück zum Zitat Kim JJ. The role of cost-effectiveness in US vaccination policy. N Engl J Med. 2011;365(19):1760–1.CrossRef Kim JJ. The role of cost-effectiveness in US vaccination policy. N Engl J Med. 2011;365(19):1760–1.CrossRef
7.
Zurück zum Zitat Smith, The structure, role, and procedures of the U.S. Advisory Committee on Immunization Practices (ACIP). Vaccine. 2010;28S:A68–75. Smith, The structure, role, and procedures of the U.S. Advisory Committee on Immunization Practices (ACIP). Vaccine. 2010;28S:A68–75.
9.
Zurück zum Zitat Markowitz LE, Dunne EF, Saraiya M, Chesson HW, Curtis CR, Gee J, Bocchini JA Jr, Unger ER. CDC human papillomavirus vaccination: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2014;63(RR05):1–30. Markowitz LE, Dunne EF, Saraiya M, Chesson HW, Curtis CR, Gee J, Bocchini JA Jr, Unger ER. CDC human papillomavirus vaccination: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2014;63(RR05):1–30.
10.
Zurück zum Zitat Nuorti JP, Whitney CG. CDC prevention of pneumococcal disease among infants and children—use of 13-valent pneumococcal conjugate vaccine and 23-valent pneumococcal polysaccharide vaccine: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2010;59(RR11):1–18. Nuorti JP, Whitney CG. CDC prevention of pneumococcal disease among infants and children—use of 13-valent pneumococcal conjugate vaccine and 23-valent pneumococcal polysaccharide vaccine: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2010;59(RR11):1–18.
11.
Zurück zum Zitat Fiore AE, Shay DK, Broder K, Iskander JK, Uyeki TM, Mootrey G, Bresee JS, Cox NJ. CDC prevention and control of seasonal influenza with vaccines: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP), 2009. Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2009;58(RR08):1–52. Fiore AE, Shay DK, Broder K, Iskander JK, Uyeki TM, Mootrey G, Bresee JS, Cox NJ. CDC prevention and control of seasonal influenza with vaccines: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP), 2009. Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2009;58(RR08):1–52.
12.
Zurück zum Zitat Guo A, Patel M, Lee GM, Moore K, Belongia EA, Harpaz R. CDC recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices for use of herpes zoster vaccines. Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2018;67(3):103–8.CrossRef Guo A, Patel M, Lee GM, Moore K, Belongia EA, Harpaz R. CDC recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices for use of herpes zoster vaccines. Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2018;67(3):103–8.CrossRef
13.
Zurück zum Zitat van de Beek D, et al. Community-acquired bacterial meningitis. Nat Rev Dis Prim. 2016;2:16074.CrossRef van de Beek D, et al. Community-acquired bacterial meningitis. Nat Rev Dis Prim. 2016;2:16074.CrossRef
15.
Zurück zum Zitat MacNeil JR, et al. Current epidemiology and trends in meningococcal disease-United States, 1996–2015. Clin Infect Dis. 2018;66(8):1276–81.CrossRef MacNeil JR, et al. Current epidemiology and trends in meningococcal disease-United States, 1996–2015. Clin Infect Dis. 2018;66(8):1276–81.CrossRef
16.
Zurück zum Zitat Nadel S, Ninis N. Invasive meningococcal disease in the vaccine era. Front Pediatr. 2018;6:321.CrossRef Nadel S, Ninis N. Invasive meningococcal disease in the vaccine era. Front Pediatr. 2018;6:321.CrossRef
17.
Zurück zum Zitat Cohn AC, MacNeil JR, Clark TA, Ortega-Sanchez IR, Briere EZ, Meissner HC, Baker CJ, Messonnier NE. CDC prevention and control of meningococcal disease: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). MMWR. 2013;62(RR02):1–22.PubMed Cohn AC, MacNeil JR, Clark TA, Ortega-Sanchez IR, Briere EZ, Meissner HC, Baker CJ, Messonnier NE. CDC prevention and control of meningococcal disease: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). MMWR. 2013;62(RR02):1–22.PubMed
18.
Zurück zum Zitat Pasteur Sanofi. Menactra [package insert]. PA: Swiftwater; 2014. Pasteur Sanofi. Menactra [package insert]. PA: Swiftwater; 2014.
19.
Zurück zum Zitat Novartis vaccines and diagnostics, Menveo [package insert]. Cambridge, MA. 2010. Novartis vaccines and diagnostics, Menveo [package insert]. Cambridge, MA. 2010.
20.
Zurück zum Zitat Weinstein MC. How much are Americans willing to pay for a quality-adjusted life year? Med Care. 2008;46(4):343–5.CrossRef Weinstein MC. How much are Americans willing to pay for a quality-adjusted life year? Med Care. 2008;46(4):343–5.CrossRef
21.
Zurück zum Zitat Eichler HG, et al. Use of cost-effectiveness analysis in health-care resource allocation decision-making: how are cost-effectiveness thresholds expected to emerge? Value Health. 2004;7(5):518–28.CrossRef Eichler HG, et al. Use of cost-effectiveness analysis in health-care resource allocation decision-making: how are cost-effectiveness thresholds expected to emerge? Value Health. 2004;7(5):518–28.CrossRef
22.
Zurück zum Zitat Neumann PJ, Cohen JT, Weinstein MC. Updating cost-effectiveness—the curious resilience of the $50,000-per-QALY threshold. N Engl J Med. 2014;371(9):796–7.CrossRef Neumann PJ, Cohen JT, Weinstein MC. Updating cost-effectiveness—the curious resilience of the $50,000-per-QALY threshold. N Engl J Med. 2014;371(9):796–7.CrossRef
23.
Zurück zum Zitat MacNeil JR, Rubin L, Folaranmi T, Ortega-Sanchez IR, Patel M, Martin SW. CDC Use Of Serogroup B meningococcal vaccines in adolescents and young adults: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2015;64(41):1171–6.CrossRef MacNeil JR, Rubin L, Folaranmi T, Ortega-Sanchez IR, Patel M, Martin SW. CDC Use Of Serogroup B meningococcal vaccines in adolescents and young adults: recommendations of the advisory committee on immunization practices (ACIP). Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep. 2015;64(41):1171–6.CrossRef
24.
Zurück zum Zitat Gold MRS, Joanna E, Russell LB, Weinstein M. Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 1996. p. 425. Gold MRS, Joanna E, Russell LB, Weinstein M. Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 1996. p. 425.
25.
Zurück zum Zitat Perera B. Efficacy and cost effectiveness of inhaled steroids in asthma in a developing country. Arch Dis Child. 1995;72(4):312–6.CrossRef Perera B. Efficacy and cost effectiveness of inhaled steroids in asthma in a developing country. Arch Dis Child. 1995;72(4):312–6.CrossRef
26.
Zurück zum Zitat Delea TE, Amdahl J, Wang A, et al. Cost effectiveness of dabrafenib as a first-line treatment in patients with BRAF V600 mutation-positive unresectable or metastatic melanoma in Canada. Pharmacoeconomics. 2015;33(4):367–80.CrossRef Delea TE, Amdahl J, Wang A, et al. Cost effectiveness of dabrafenib as a first-line treatment in patients with BRAF V600 mutation-positive unresectable or metastatic melanoma in Canada. Pharmacoeconomics. 2015;33(4):367–80.CrossRef
27.
Zurück zum Zitat Neumann PJ, et al. Growth and quality of the cost–utility literature, 1976–2001. Value Health. 2005;8(1):3–9.CrossRef Neumann PJ, et al. Growth and quality of the cost–utility literature, 1976–2001. Value Health. 2005;8(1):3–9.CrossRef
28.
Zurück zum Zitat Pliskin JS, Shepard DS, Weinstein MC. Utility functions for life years and health status. Oper Res. 1980;28(1):206–24.CrossRef Pliskin JS, Shepard DS, Weinstein MC. Utility functions for life years and health status. Oper Res. 1980;28(1):206–24.CrossRef
29.
30.
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman D, Tversky A. Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica. 1979;47(2):263–91.CrossRef Kahneman D, Tversky A. Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica. 1979;47(2):263–91.CrossRef
31.
Zurück zum Zitat Bleichrodt H, Wakker P, Johannesson M. Characterizing QALYs by risk neutrality. J Risk Uncertainty. 1997;15(2):107–14.CrossRef Bleichrodt H, Wakker P, Johannesson M. Characterizing QALYs by risk neutrality. J Risk Uncertainty. 1997;15(2):107–14.CrossRef
32.
Zurück zum Zitat Hoel M. Allocating health care resources when people are risk averse with respect to life time. Health Econ. 2003;12(7):601–8.CrossRef Hoel M. Allocating health care resources when people are risk averse with respect to life time. Health Econ. 2003;12(7):601–8.CrossRef
33.
Zurück zum Zitat Dolan P, et al. QALY maximisation and people’s preferences: a methodological review of the literature. Health Econ. 2005;14(2):197–208.CrossRef Dolan P, et al. QALY maximisation and people’s preferences: a methodological review of the literature. Health Econ. 2005;14(2):197–208.CrossRef
34.
Zurück zum Zitat Williams A. Intergenerational equity: an exploration of the ‘fair innings’ argument. Health Econ. 1997;6(2):117–32.CrossRef Williams A. Intergenerational equity: an exploration of the ‘fair innings’ argument. Health Econ. 1997;6(2):117–32.CrossRef
35.
Zurück zum Zitat Pettitt DA, Naughton B, Roscoe A, Ramakrishnan A, Ali A, Davies B, Dopson S, Hollander G, Smith JA, Brindley DA. The limitations of QALY: a literature review. J Stem Cell Res Ther. 2016;6(4):1–7. Pettitt DA, Naughton B, Roscoe A, Ramakrishnan A, Ali A, Davies B, Dopson S, Hollander G, Smith JA, Brindley DA. The limitations of QALY: a literature review. J Stem Cell Res Ther. 2016;6(4):1–7.
36.
Zurück zum Zitat Hellinger FJ. Expected utility theory and risky choices with health outcomes. Med Care. 1989;27(3):273–9.CrossRef Hellinger FJ. Expected utility theory and risky choices with health outcomes. Med Care. 1989;27(3):273–9.CrossRef
37.
Zurück zum Zitat Eraker SA, Sox H Jr. Assessment of patients’ preferences for therapeutic outcomes. Med Decis Making. 1980;1(1):29–39.CrossRef Eraker SA, Sox H Jr. Assessment of patients’ preferences for therapeutic outcomes. Med Decis Making. 1980;1(1):29–39.CrossRef
38.
Zurück zum Zitat Johannesson M, Johansson P-O. Is the valuation of a QALY gained independent of age? Some empirical evidence. J Health Econ. 1997;16(5):589–99.CrossRef Johannesson M, Johansson P-O. Is the valuation of a QALY gained independent of age? Some empirical evidence. J Health Econ. 1997;16(5):589–99.CrossRef
39.
Zurück zum Zitat Mooney G, Jan S, Wiseman V. Examining preferences for allocating health care gains. Health Care Anal. 1995;3(3):261–5.CrossRef Mooney G, Jan S, Wiseman V. Examining preferences for allocating health care gains. Health Care Anal. 1995;3(3):261–5.CrossRef
40.
Zurück zum Zitat Kaimal AJ, et al. Cost-effectiveness of private umbilical cord blood banking. Obstet Gynecol. 2009;114(4):848–55.CrossRef Kaimal AJ, et al. Cost-effectiveness of private umbilical cord blood banking. Obstet Gynecol. 2009;114(4):848–55.CrossRef
41.
Zurück zum Zitat Petrini C. Umbilical cord blood banking: from personal donation to international public registries to global bioeconomy. J Blood Med. 2014;5:87.CrossRef Petrini C. Umbilical cord blood banking: from personal donation to international public registries to global bioeconomy. J Blood Med. 2014;5:87.CrossRef
43.
Zurück zum Zitat Dardis R, Aaronson S, Lin Y-N. Cost-benefit analysis of flammability standards. Am J Agr Econ. 1978;60(4):695–700.CrossRef Dardis R, Aaronson S, Lin Y-N. Cost-benefit analysis of flammability standards. Am J Agr Econ. 1978;60(4):695–700.CrossRef
44.
Zurück zum Zitat Tengs TO, et al. Five-hundred life-saving interventions and their cost-effectiveness. Risk Anal. 1995;15(3):369–90.CrossRef Tengs TO, et al. Five-hundred life-saving interventions and their cost-effectiveness. Risk Anal. 1995;15(3):369–90.CrossRef
45.
Zurück zum Zitat National Research Council (U.S.). Transportation Research Board., Improving school bus safety. Special report/Transportation Research Board, National Research Council. 1989. Washington, D.C.: Transportation Research Board, National Research Council; 1989. p. 214. National Research Council (U.S.). Transportation Research Board., Improving school bus safety. Special report/Transportation Research Board, National Research Council. 1989. Washington, D.C.: Transportation Research Board, National Research Council; 1989. p. 214.
46.
Zurück zum Zitat Binstock R, George L. Hand book of aging and social science. New York: Academic Press; 2011. Binstock R, George L. Hand book of aging and social science. New York: Academic Press; 2011.
47.
Zurück zum Zitat Aldridge MD, Kelley AS. The myth regarding the high cost of end-of-life care. Am J Public Health. 2015;105(12):2411–5.CrossRef Aldridge MD, Kelley AS. The myth regarding the high cost of end-of-life care. Am J Public Health. 2015;105(12):2411–5.CrossRef
48.
Zurück zum Zitat Bloom DE, et al. Commentary: why has uptake of pneumococcal vaccines for children been so slow? The Perils of undervaluation. Pediatr Infect Dis J. 2020;39(2):145–56.CrossRef Bloom DE, et al. Commentary: why has uptake of pneumococcal vaccines for children been so slow? The Perils of undervaluation. Pediatr Infect Dis J. 2020;39(2):145–56.CrossRef
50.
Zurück zum Zitat Christensen H, et al. Economic evaluation of meningococcal vaccines: considerations for the future. Eur J Health Econ. 2020;21(2):297–309.CrossRef Christensen H, et al. Economic evaluation of meningococcal vaccines: considerations for the future. Eur J Health Econ. 2020;21(2):297–309.CrossRef
52.
Zurück zum Zitat Stewart MG, Ellingwood BR, Mueller J. Homeland security: a case study in risk aversion for public decision-making. Int J Risk Assess Manag. 2011;15(5):367–86.CrossRef Stewart MG, Ellingwood BR, Mueller J. Homeland security: a case study in risk aversion for public decision-making. Int J Risk Assess Manag. 2011;15(5):367–86.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Pediatric Vaccines and Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds: How Much is Too Much to Pay for Prevention?
verfasst von
Jordan Amdahl
Derek Weycker
Ray Farkouh
Liping Huang
Caitlin Eichten
Gerry Oster
Publikationsdatum
10.11.2020
Verlag
Springer Healthcare
Erschienen in
Infectious Diseases and Therapy / Ausgabe 1/2021
Print ISSN: 2193-8229
Elektronische ISSN: 2193-6382
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s40121-020-00367-6

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2021

Infectious Diseases and Therapy 1/2021 Zur Ausgabe

Leitlinien kompakt für die Innere Medizin

Mit medbee Pocketcards sicher entscheiden.

Seit 2022 gehört die medbee GmbH zum Springer Medizin Verlag

Update Innere Medizin

Bestellen Sie unseren Fach-Newsletter und bleiben Sie gut informiert.