Skip to main content
Log in

When normative and descriptive diverge: how to bridge the difference

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Revealed preferences are not consistent. Many anomalies have been found in different contexts. This finding leads to a divergence between normative and descriptive analyses. There are several ways of facing this problem. In this paper we argue in favour of debiasing observed choices in such a way that the “true” preferences are discovered. Our procedure is based on quantitative corrections derived from assuming the descriptive validity of prospect theory and the normative validity of expected utility theory. Those corrective formulas were first applied by Bleichrodt et al. (Manag Sci 47:1498–1514, 2001). We explain here how such formulas can be used to avoid inefficient allocation of health care resources. This approach shares the philosophy of libertarian paternalism (LP). However, it reduces some of the potential problems of LP: the definition of error (and the need to nudge people) is more clear and objective. In this sense, it reduces the chances that the regulator tries to nudge people toward behaviour based on her preferences rather than those of the people she is nudging.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abellán-Perpiñán JM, Pinto-Prades JL, Méndez-Martínez I, Badía X (2006) Towards a better QALY model. Health Econ 15: 665–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abellan-Perpiñan JM, Bleichrodt H, Pinto-Prades JL (2009) The predictive validity of prospect theory versus expected utility in health utility measurement. J Health Econ 28: 1039–1047

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais M (1953) Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine. Econometrica 21: 503–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Rangel A (2005) Behavioral public economics: welfare and policy analysis with non-standard decision-makers. NBER Working Paper No. 11518 July

  • Beshears J, Choi JJ, Laibson D, Madrian BC (2008) How are preferences revealed. J Publ Econ 92 (8–9): 1787–1794

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum MH (2008) New paradoxes of risky decision making. Psychol Rev 115(2): 463–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt H, Pinto JL (2000) A parameter-free elicitation of the probability weighting function in medical decision analysis. Manag Sci 46: 1485–1496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt H, Quiggin J (1997) Characterizing QALYs under a general rank dependent utility model. J Risk Uncertain 15: 151–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt H, Pinto JL, Wakker P (2001) Making descriptive use of prospect theory to improve the prescriptive use of expected utility. Manag Sci 47: 1498–1514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt H, Abellan-Perpiñan JM, Pinto-Prades JL, Mendez-Martinez I (2007) Resolving inconsistencies in utility measurement under risk: tests of generalizations of expected utility. Manag Sci 53: 469–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Booij AS, Van Praag BMS, Vande Kuilen G (2010) A parametric analysis of prospect theorys functionals for the general population. Theory Decis 68(1): 115–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braga J, Starmer C (2005) Preference anomalies, preference elicitation and the discovered preference hypothesis. Environ Resour Econ 32: 55–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braga J, Humphrey SJ, Starmer C (2009) Market experience eliminates some anomalies-and creates new ones. Eur Econ Rev 53: 401–416

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brazier J, Roberts J, Deverill M (2002) The estimation of a preference-based measure of health from the SF-36. J Health Econ 21: 271–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF (1995) Individual decision making. In: Kagel J, Roth AE Hanbook of experimental economics. Princenton University Press, Princenton

  • Cox JC, Grether DM (1996) The preference reversal phenomenon: response mode, markets and incentives. Econ Theory 7: 381–405

    Google Scholar 

  • Diecidue E, Wakker PP (2001) On the intuition of rank-dependent utility. J Risk Uncertain 23: 281–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolan P (2000) The measurement of health-related quality of life for use in resource allocation decisions in health care. In: Culyer AJ, Newhouse JP (eds) (eds) Handbook of health economics, vol 1B. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 1723–1760

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolan P, Kahneman D (2008) Interpetations of utility and their implications for the valuation of health. Econ J 118: 215–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ 75: 643–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feeny DH, Furlong WJ, Torrance GW et al (2002) Multiattribute and single-attribute utility functions for the Health Utilities Index Mark 3 system. Med Care 40: 113–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez R, Wu G (1999) On the shape of the probability weighting function. Cogn Psychol 38: 129–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi JC (1955) Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. J Polit Econ 63: 309–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hershey JC, Schoemaker PJ (1985) Probability versus certainty equivalence methods in utility measurement: are they equivalent?. Manag Sci 31: 1213–1231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1979) Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47: 263–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch J, Tang FF, Thaler R (2001) The endowment effect and repeated market trials: is the Vickrey auction demand revealing?. Exper Econ 4: 257–269

    Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling V, Wakker PP (2005) An index of loss aversion. J Econ Theory 122: 119–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larrick RP (2004) Debiasing. In: Koehler DJ, Harvey N (eds) (eds) Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 316–337

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes G (2010) Modeling choice and valuation in decision experiments. Psychol Rev 117(3): 902–924

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes G, Starmer C, Sugden R (2003) Do anomalies disappear in repeated markets?. Econ J 113: 153–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell G (2005) Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Nw UL Rev 99: 1245–1817

    Google Scholar 

  • Pliskin JS, Shepard DS, Weinstein MC (1980) Utility functions for life years and health status. Oper Res 28: 206–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott CP (1996) Rational individual behavior in markets and social choice processes. In: Arrow KJ, Colombatto E, Perlman M, Schmidt C (eds) The rational foundations of economic behavior: proceedings of the IEA conference held in Turin, Italy. St Martin’s Press, New York, pp 225–250

  • Plott CR, Zeiler K (2005) The willingness to pay–willingness to accept gap, the ‘endowment effect’, subject misconceptions, and experimental procedures for eliciting valuations. Am Econ Rev 95: 530–545

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prelec D (1998) The probability weighting function. Econometrica 66: 497–528

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson A, Loomes G, Jones-Lee M (2001) Visual analog scales, standard gambles, and relative risk aversion. Med Decis Making 21: 17–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1954) The foundations of statistics. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shalev J (2000) Loss aversion equilibrium. Int J Game Theory 29: 269–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogren J, Cho S, Koo C, List J, Park C, Polo P, Wilhelmi R (2001) Auction mechanisms and the measurement of WTP and WTA. Resour Energy Econ 23: 97–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalmeier PFM, Bezembinder TGG (1999) The discrepancy between risky and riskless utilities: a matter of framing?. Med Decis Making 19: 435–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer C (2000) Developments in Non-expected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. J Econ Lit 38: 332–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2005) Coping with preference anomalies in cost–benefit analysis: a market-simulation approach. Environ Resour Econ 32: 129–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2009) On nudging: a review of nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth and happiness by richard H. Thaler and cass R. Sunstein. Int J Econ Bus 16(3): 365–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C, Thaler R (2003) Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. Univ Chic Law Rev 70: 1159–1202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (1992) Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty. J Risk Uncertain 5: 297–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2003) Libertarian paternalism. Am Econ Rev 93(2): 175–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Osch S, van den Hout W, Stiggelbout AM (2006) Exploring the reference point in prospect theory: gambles for length of life. Med Decis Making 26: 338–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Kuilen G (2009) Subjective probability weighting and the discovered preference hypothesis. Theory Decis 67: 1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker PP (2010) Prospect theory: for risk and ambiguity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker PP, Köbberling V, Schwieren C (2007) Prospect-theory’s diminishing sensitivity versus economics’ intrinsic utility of money: how the introduction of the euro can be used to disentangle the two empirically. Theory Decis 63: 205–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jose-Luis Pinto-Prades.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pinto-Prades, JL., Abellan-Perpiñan, JM. When normative and descriptive diverge: how to bridge the difference. Soc Choice Welf 38, 569–584 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-012-0655-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-012-0655-5

Keywords

Navigation