Skip to main content
Log in

Researching Preferences, Valuation and Hypothetical Bias

  • Published:
Environmental and Resource Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A number of recent papers in environmental economics have focused on the process of researching preferences – agents are uncertain about preferences but with effort may narrow their uncertainty. This issue has arisen in formulating bids in contingent valuation (CV) as well as the debate over the divergence between WTP and WTA. In the context of CV, it has been suggested that the hypothetical nature of the preference elicitation process biases responses. This paper provides both a theoretical model and experimental evidence to contribute to this debate. The model is a model of competitive bidding for a private good with two components that are particularly relevant to the debate. The first component is that bidders are unsure of their own value for the private good but may purchase information about their own value (researching preferences). The second component is that there is a probability that the auction is hypothetical – that the winning bidder will not get the private good and will not pay the winning bid. The experiment tests this theoretical model of bidding equilibrium and analyzes the effects of variations in the parameters (hypotheticalness, information costs and number of agents) on the endogenous variables (such as the proportion of bidders who become informed and the winning bid). Experimental results suggest that an increase in the hypotheticalness of an auction tends to decrease the likelihood that bidders pay for information on their valuation with an ambiguous effect on the winning bid.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bajari P., Hortescu A. (2004) Economic Insights from Internet Auctions. Journal of Economic Literature 42:457–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson R. T., Flores N. E., Meade N. F. (2001) Contingent Valuation: Controversies and Evidence. Environmental and Resource Economics 19:173–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummings R. G., Harrison G. W. (1994) Was the Ohio Court Well Informed in its Assessment of the Accuracy of the Contingent Valuation Method?. Natural Resources Journal 34:1

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyer D., Kagel J. H., Levin D. (1989) Resolving Uncertainty about the Number of Bidders in Independent Private-value Auctions: An Experimental Analysis. Rand Journal of Economics 20:268–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelbrecht-Wiggans R., Milgrom P. R., Weber R. J. (1983) Competitive Bidding and Proprietary Information. Journal of Mathematical Economics 11(2):161–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossman S. J., Stiglitz J. E. (1980) On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets. AER 70:393–408

    Google Scholar 

  • Guzman, R. M. and Kolstad, C. D. (1997), “A Model of Auction Equilibrium with Costly Information Acquisition,” Working Paper # 17–97, Dept. of Economics, University of California at Santa Barbara. [www.econ.ucsb.edu/papers/wp17–97.edf]

  • Hansen R. G., Lott J. R. (1991) The Winner’s Curse and Public Information in Common Value Auctions: Comment. American Economic Review 81:347–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagel J.H., Harstad R.M., Levin D. (1987) Information Impact and Allocation Rules in Auctions with Affiliated Private Values: A Laboratory Study. Econometrica 55:1275–1304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolstad C. D., Guzman R. M. (1999) Information and the Divergence between Willingness-to-Accept and Willingness-to-Pay. JEEM 38:66–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee T. K. (1985) Competition and Information Acquisition in First Price Auctions. Economics Letters 18:129–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, S. A. (1984), “Information Acquisition in Discriminatory Auctions,” in M. Boyer and R. Kihlstrom, eds., Bayesian Models in Economic Theory. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

  • Milgrom Paul. (1981) Rational Expectations, Information Acquisition, and Competitive Bidding. Econometrica 49(4):921–943

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P., Weber R. P. (1982) A Theory of Auctions and Competitive Bidding. Econometrica 50(5):1089–1122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkes D. C. (2005) Auction Design with Costly Preference Elicitation. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 44:269–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persico N. (2000) Information Acquisition in Auctions. Econometrica 68:135–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin M. (2000) Risk Aversion and Expected-Utility Theory: A Calibration Theorem. Econometrica 68:1281–1292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer U., Ungern-Sternberg T. Von (1983) Sealed Bid Auctions and the Search for Better Information. Economica 50:79–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senter, R. J. (1992), Analysis of Data: Introductory Statistics for Behavioral Sciences. Scott, Foresman, and Company, 1969, eds., Handbook of Game Theory, Volume 1. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

  • Zhao J. H., Kling C. L. (2001) A New Explanation for the WTP/WTA Controversy. Economics Letters 73:293–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research supported in part by grants from the Research Board of the University of Illinois, the Academic Senate of the University of California, and NSF Grant SBR-9496303. The authors gratefully acknowledge the provision of an experimental economics laboratory and computer support services by the Commerce Research Office of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. We also appreciate helpful suggestions from John Braden and Anne Villamil. However, none of them bears responsibilities for shortcomings. We also wish to thank two anonymous referees for very helpful suggestions. We would also like to express our appreciation to John List for encouraging us to persevere with this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Charles D. Kolstad.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 2

Consider the equilibrium condition (2) as an implicit function in p and N, and – just for the sake of exposition – assume that the first inequality holds as equality. Then, the equilibrium condition is:

$$H(p,N)=0$$
(A.1)

where the function H is defined as

$$H(p,N)\equiv\Omega(\Pi(p,N))-p$$
(A.2)

Therefore,

$$ \frac{{\hbox{d}}p}{{\hbox{d}}N}=-\frac{\partial H/\partial N}{\partial H/\partial p} =-\frac{(\partial\Omega/\partial\Pi)(\partial\Pi/\partial N)} {(\partial\Omega/\partial\Pi)(\partial\Pi/\partial p)-1}\ge 0 $$
(A.3)

Now, since the equilibrium p, p e, increases with N (provided Ω is not “flat”), it follows from the expressions (A.1)–(A.2) and the monotonicity of Ω that the equilibrium value of Π(p e, N) should be smaller the greater the value of N. Since the density function f has not changed, this is only possible through an increase of the exponent [(1−p)N−1] in expression (1).

Proof of Proposition 3

Let us define:

$$N^{\ast}\equiv (1-p)N$$
(A.4)

and

$$B(z, N^{\ast})=z-\int\frac{z}{V} \{\frac{F(\Theta)}{F(z)}\}^{[N^{\ast}-1]}{\hbox{d}}\Theta \quad \hbox{if}\,z\ge \overline{V\,} $$
(A.5a)
$$ =\overline{V\,}\quad \hbox{if}\,z\ge\overline{V\,} $$
(A.5b)

clearly,

$$ (i)\quad \frac{\partial B(z,N^{\ast})}{\partial z}\ge 0 $$
(A.6a)
$$ (ii)\quad \frac{\partial B(z,N^{\ast})}{\partial N^{\ast}}\ge 0 $$
(A.6b)

and that the expectation of the winner bid can be written simply as:

$$ (iii)\quad E(b)=\mathop{\int}\nolimits^{V_{\rm u}}_{V_{\rm l}}B(z,N^{\ast}) \gamma_{N^{\ast}}(z){\hbox{d}}z $$
(A.6c)

Now,

$$ \frac{{\hbox{d}}E(b)}{{\hbox{d}}N}=\frac{{\hbox{d}}E(b)}{{\hbox{d}}N^{\ast}}\cdot\frac{{\hbox{d}}N^{*}}{{\hbox{d}}N} $$
(A.7)

From the proof of Proposition 2, we already know that the second factor is positive. Thus, it suffices to prove that the first is non-negative. Differentiating (A.6c), we can say that:

$$\frac{{\hbox{d}}E(b)}{{\hbox{d}}N^{*}}=\int\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}\frac{\partial B(z,N^{*})}{\partial N} \gamma(z){\hbox{d}}z+\int\nolimits^{V_{\rm u}}_{V_{\rm l}} B(z,N^{*})\frac{\partial \gamma(z)}{\partial N^{*}}{\hbox{d}}z $$
(A.8)

where, for notation convenience, the subscript of the density function γ N* has been dropped. It follows from (A.6b) that the first term in this expression is nonnegative. In turn, the second term can be written as:

$$ \mathop{\int}\nolimits_{0}^{V_{\rm u}}B(z,N^{*})\frac{\partial \gamma(z)}{\partial N^{*}}{\hbox{d}}z \equiv \mathop{\int}\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}B(z,N^{*})\frac{\partial}{\partial N^{*}}\left(\frac{\partial \Gamma(z)}{\partial z}\right){\hbox{d}}z $$
$$ \equiv \mathop{\int}\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}B(z,N^{*})\frac{\partial}{\partial z} \left(\frac{\partial \Gamma(z)}{\partial N^{*}}\right){\hbox{d}}z $$
(A.9)

which, by straightforward integration by part, yields:

$$ \equiv B(z,N^{*})\left(\frac{\partial \Gamma(Z)}{\partial N^{*}}\right)|_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}-\mathop{\int}\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}\frac{\partial B(z,N^{*})}{\partial z}\frac{\partial \Gamma(z)}{\partial N^{*}}{\hbox{d}}z $$
(A.10)

Finally, we use the fact that, for all \(N^{\ast}\), \(\Gamma (V)=0\) and \(\Gamma (V)=1\), so that its derivative at those points is zero. Therefore, we end with:

$$ \mathop{\int}\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}B(z,N^{*})\frac{\partial \gamma(z)} {\partial N^{*}}= -\mathop{\int}\nolimits_{V_{\rm l}}^{V_{\rm u}}\mathop{\frac{\partial B(z,N^{*})}{\partial z}}\limits_{(+)}\mathop{\frac{\partial}{\partial N^{*}}(F(z)^{N^{*}})}\limits_{(-)}{\hbox{d}}z \ge 0 $$
(A.11)

and the result follows immediately.

Proof of Proposition 4

For this case, it is convenient to rewrite the equilibrium condition (A.2) as:

$$p^{\rm e}=1 - \hbox{G}(\Pi (p^{\rm e})) $$
(A.12)

where G is the cumulative function corresponding to the density g. Next, let us begin by considering an arbitrary change in g. Since \(\Pi(p^{\rm e})\) is not affected by the changes in g, it follows that changes in the initial equilibrium p e depend only on changes of G(Π(p)) when evaluated at that point. Formally, consider two different distribution functions, G0 and G1, with p 0 and p 1 as the corresponding equilibrium proportions of informed bidders. Clearly

$$ \Omega_{1}(\Pi(p_{0})) \ge \Omega_{0}(\Pi (p_{0})) \quad \hbox{iff}\quad \hbox{G}_{0}(\Pi(p_{0})) \ge \hbox{G}_{1}(\Pi (p_{0})) $$
(A.13)

where the subscript {0, 1} identifies the pre- and post-change functions. Therefore, p 1p 0 iff G1(Π (p 0)) ≤ G0(Π (p 0)).

The intuition behind this is obvious. For any value of p, including the equilibrium p e, the value of information is independent of G. Thus, the original equilibrium can only be changed with changes in the proportion of bidders with information costs below or above the corresponding value of information.

To advance a further step, consider the case where changes in g induce an increase in p e and, consequently, a decrease in [(1−p)N−1]. The latter effect acts in the same way as an exogenous decrease of N. Hence, it causes a decrease of the integral in the expression (Equation (3)) for the expected winning bid, E(b), and a simultaneous shift of mass of the density \(\gamma_{N^{\ast}}\) to the left. Of course, to have a strict change of p, the change in G must be big enough to overcome the discrete nature of p.

Proof of Proposition 5

The proof of this proposition hinges on showing the proportion of bidders choosing to become informed is the same in the two cases – the hypothetical case where the probability the auction is real is α and the information costs are distributed as g(x) and the real case with the auction definitely real and information costs distributed as \(\hat g(x) \equiv \alpha g(\alpha x)\). If the proportion of bidders is the same, then bids will be unaffected by the fact that after the auction a lottery is held to determine if the auction was real.

Equation (3) defines the proportion of informed bidders in the hypothetical case, except that profits must be diluted by the probability that the auction is real, α:

$$ \Omega(\alpha \Pi(p^{e})) \ge p^{e};\quad p^{e}+\frac{1}{N}\ge \Omega(\alpha \Pi(p^{e}+\frac{1}{N})) $$
(A.14)

With the purely real auction, costs are distributed as \(\hat g(x) \equiv \alpha g(\alpha x)\) which implies \(\hat{\Omega}(x)\equiv \Omega (\alpha x)\). It is easy to see that this implies that the conditions defining the proportion of informed bidders in the purely real auction are the same as in Equation A.14. Thus the two auctions yield identical outcomes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Guzman, R.M., Kolstad, C.D. Researching Preferences, Valuation and Hypothetical Bias. Environ Resource Econ 37, 465–487 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-006-9034-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-006-9034-y

Keywords

JEL categories

Navigation