Skip to main content
Log in

Soft paternalism, merit goods, and normative individualism

  • Published:
European Journal of Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Paternalism is an attempt to influence individuals’ decisions for their own benefit, even if there are no third parties involved. This seems to contradict normative individualism, which provides the general orientation to our modern democracies. Soft or libertarian paternalism accepts the necessity of paternalism due to the existence of behavioural anomalies, but intends to apply only such measures that do not restrict the decision leeway of individuals. Nevertheless, the same objections that can be raised against its strong version can also be raised against soft paternalism. On the other hand, as soon as we accept that human beings are able to reflect not only about their actions but also about the preferences guiding their actions, there is no longer a necessary contradiction between paternalism and normative individualism. As far as we know today, the possibilities to successfully apply soft paternalistic measures are rather limited. On the other hand, while some criticisms are justified, others largely overshoot the mark and seem to be at least partly ideologically motivated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In his 1957 paper he does not present a clear definition of merit goods (wants), but acknowledges that such “public policy aims at interference with individual preferences” (p. 341). In his 1987 paper he describes six different interpretations of this concept. His main preferred one is relying on “community preferences”: “consider a setting where individuals, as members of the community, accept certain community values or preferences, even though their personal preferences might differ.” (p. 452.) “… offering community values as a restraint on individual choice did, however, fit the pattern and, as I see it, goes to the heart of the merit concept. (p. 353.)—On early discussions of merit goods see also Head (1966), Andel (1984) as well as Schmidt (1988).

  2. On this, see for example Thaler (1992) as well as Kirchgässner (2014, pp. 269ff.).

  3. On this, see for example Bernheim et al. (2011). The labelling ‘401(k)’ stems from the corresponding definition of the US finance department. For income that is paid into these accounts, social security payments have to be made, but this income is not taxed. Contributions are voluntary. Taxes are only due when the insured receive payments later on. (This tax arrangement corresponds to the one of the Swiss pension system).

  4. Choi et al. (2003a, b) get similar results for three different companies. Theoretical explanations are given by Choi et al. (2003a).

  5. On the status quo bias see Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988) as well as Thaler (1992, pp. 63ff).

  6. On framing effects see Tversky and Kahneman (1981, 1987) as well as Stocké (2002).

  7. On anti-authoritarian pedagogics see, for example, Koch (2000, pp. 9ff.).

  8. It is somewhat more problematic with respect to adolescents. See for this Manson (2015).

  9. From a (traditional) economic perspective, this tends to be inefficient, because the poor man might reach a higher utility level if he is free to use this money. See, for example, Blomquist and Micheletto (2006). However, Pommerehne (1975) has shown that such a conditional transfer might be better for the recipient if this increases the donors’ willingness to make voluntary contributions.

  10. Other countries, for example the US, do not impose such an obligation. There, mandatory schooling is still seen as an obligation to offer public education. On the history of mandatory education in Germany, see, for example, Mors (1986).

  11. In many cases, definitions of paternalism do only implicitly but not explicitly imply that no interests of third parties are at stake. See, for example, Hausman and Welch (2010, p. 129) or Dworkin (2014): “Paternalism is the interference of a state or an individual with another person, against their will, and defended or motivated by a claim that the person interfered with will be better off or protected from harm”.

  12. On the introduction of soft paternalism, see for example Loewenstein and Haisley (2008), who consider this a new normative economics. The term libertarian paternalism was coined by Sunstein and Thaler (2003). On this, see also Thaler and Sunstein (2003). A different distinction between hard and soft paternalism with reference to Feinberg (1986) is, for example, provided by Pope (2004), who also defends this kind of hard paternalism. On the position of Feinberg, see also Arneson (2005).

  13. Hausman and Welch (2010) deny that providing information by “rational persuasion” is paternalistic and they contrast it with “shaping a choice” (or “manipulation”) (p. 128). However, the former is also a kind of government intervention to benefit the individual involved without effects on third parties. Thus, given the definition presented above, it is paternalistic. Correspondingly, Beck (2010, pp. 50f.) is wrong when he denies that the elimination of informational asymmetries is also an element of soft paternalism. It is, however, only paternalistic as long as no third parties are involved. As soon as informational asymmetries lead to effects on third parties, their elimination can be justified by the existence of external effects.

  14. More recently, Sunstein (2014) extended the term ‘nudge’ to any kind of trigger that provides some information or reminds us of something. He states, for example, that a GPS “should be seen as a form of means paternalism” (p. 61). Moreover, as for example in Sunstein and Reisch (2014) discussed below, nudges are proposed that are not soft and/or are not intended to promote the well-being of the individuals directly involved but have other objectives. Here, we restrict our discussion to the traditional meaning of ‘paternalism’ which implies that there is some (human) authority who tries to influence the behaviour of others. Thus, we stick to the definition of Thaler and Sunstein (2008) given above and assume that libertarian paternalism has to be soft, i.e. there is no difference between soft and libertarian paternalism.

  15. To presence the freedom of choice is necessary but not sufficient to qualify a paternalistic measure as being libertarian: A cigarette tax, for example, does not forbid smoking, but makes it more costly. Thus, there is still freedom of choice.

  16. There is also a fluid transition between medium and hard paternalism: High taxes can be interpreted as fines for deviation behaviour, while fines for not obeying a permit or prescription might be interpreted as a high tax.

  17. Hausman and Welch (2010) correctly note that not all nudges have to be paternalistic. They are not always intended to improve the decision of individuals to their own benefit. See, for example, the default rule of two-sided printing described in Sunstein and Reisch (2014, pp. XXff.). There, the objective is to reduce the amount of paper used, i.e.an environmental objective.

  18. On this in particular, see Jolls and Sunstein (2006). Though behavioural anomalies are often employed as a justification for the application of nudges, they can also justify harder paternalistic measures as, for example, the permit of trading ‘illegal’ drugs. Thus, the existence of such anomalies might be a necessary condition for using paternalistic measures, but they do not have to be libertarian ones. This depends, beside other, on the effectiveness of the measures proposed.

  19. On this, see Camerer et al. (2003). They speak of “asymmetric paternalism”.

  20. On this, see also Thaler and Sunstein (2008), as well as Ginsburg et al. (2013), who suggest temporary law as another kind of nudge.

  21. In social insurance, the existence of moral hazard or adverse selection is often used as justification of government intervention. However, behind these there are in most cases distributional considerations and/or problems of external effects and/or undersupply of public goods.

  22. Consistent with this argument, the first column of the Swiss old age pension system, the Alters- und Hinterlassenenversicherung (AHV), covers only the subsistence level. (This, of course, holds only for the maximum pension. Whenever somebody receives less than this maximum and does not have additional income and/or wealth, (s)he is entitled to receive additional payments in order to guarantee the subsistence level.).

  23. On this, see for example de Pury et al. (1995, pp. 62ff.).

  24. On estimations of the external effects of road traffic, see for example, Quinet (2004).

  25. The revenue that the 144 German theatre and opera houses took in through ticket sales covered only about 17 per cent of total expenditure in the season 2008/2009. On average, each ticket was subsidised by € 99.31. Source of the data: Statistical Yearbook 2011 for Germany, Table 7.6, p. 180.

  26. Those members of the lower classes who, due to their low income, do not have to pay direct taxes might not be directly affected. They might, however, be affected indirectly whenever, in order to finance these subsidies, indirect taxes are increased and/or the government cuts services and/or payments that would have benefitted these people.

  27. On such an argument, see for example Withers (1979).

  28. On possible justifications for public subsidies for the arts, see for example Frey and Pommerehne (1990). Despite his heavy criticism of libertarian paternalism, these subsidies are also defended by Rebonato (2012, p. 249).

  29. As mentioned above, relying on “community values” is his most preferred interpretation of merit goods. As another alternative, he at least mentions the possibility of “multiple preferences or ‘higher values’” and also refers to Brennan and Lomasky (1983), but without discussing their approach. On the problem of group preferences independent of those of the individuals involved see also Kirchgässner (2008, pp. 205ff.).

  30. On this, see for example Leonard (2008), or, in German speaking countries, Tietzel and Müller (1998), as well as Schnellenbach (2011, 2012).

  31. See, for example, Dworkin (2005), who speaks of “moral paternalism”, but also Pope (Pope 2004, 2005a, b), Shafer-Landau (2005), Marneffe (2006), Sacha (2007), or Glod (2008). But see also Rebonato (2012, 2013) who defends some kinds of medium paternalism but nevertheless criticizes libertarian paternalism because it “does not live up with its claim of being a benign, ‘safe’ and unobtrusive ‘real-Third-Way’ alternative to both paternalism and liberalism” (2013, p. 56).

  32. On this see Kultgen (2014).

  33. That people dislike the behaviour of others and are insofar (mentally) negatively affected by their behaviour is no valid argument for government intervention given the principles of normative individualism. See, for example, the definition of individual rights in Sen (1970). For “A Liberal Argument for Slavery” see, for example, Philmore (1982) or Kershnar (2003).

  34. On a short history of the philosophical tradition, see also Brennan and Lomasky (1983, pp. 195f.).

  35. See also Jeffrey (1974), Hirschman (1984) or George (1998) who all refer to Frankfurt (1971). Sen (1977) argues in a similar way with a hierarchy of preferences that even includes more than two levels.

  36. On this, see the classical contribution by Elster (1979), but also Elster (2000) as well as Schelling (1978, 1980).

  37. On this, see also Kirchgässner (1992, 2010).

  38. An alternative is presented by Grüne-Yanoff (2009) who, in his integrity approach, distinguishes for the case of inconsistent preferences more from less central ones proposes a reordering “which respects people’s core preferences and reconstructs a consistent preference ordering around them” (p. 19).

  39. Grüne-Yanoff (2012) denies this and claims that there is a (necessary) conflict between libertarian paternalism and liberal principles, but he does not take into account the approach of Brennan and Lomasky (1983).

  40. Even Wicksell (1896), who—in principle—demanded unanimity for such decisions, accepted that “absolute unanimity may have to be ruled out for practical reasons” (p. 92).

  41. On this, see for example van Aaken (2006).

  42. On this “distinction in our thinking between the constitutional level of the discourse, evaluation, or choice and the post-constitutional level”, see also Buchanan (1986, p. 86).

  43. On this, see for example the suggestions in Thaler and Sunstein (2008), or, with special reference to the Netherlands, Korman and Prast (2010).

  44. On optimal sin taxes that relate, however, to the consumption of potato chips, see O’Donoghue and Rabin (2006).

  45. On the possibilities of soft paternalism to reduce smoking, see also Lucas (2012).

  46. On this, see Cutler et al. (2003) for the US and Brunello et al. (2009) for Europe.

  47. See, for example, Drèze et al. (1994) or Chandon et al. (2009).

  48. Investigating supermarkets in Melbourne, Dixon et al. (2006) show that high-energy food is often placed close to cash points; this is to induce children to ask their parents to buy these for them. On the other hand, Just and Payne (2009) believe that there are possibilities to have such an impact on consumers without reducing the profits.

  49. On this, see for example Downs et al. (2009) as well as Wisdom et al. (2010).

  50. On this, see for example Loewenstein et al. (2007), Just and Payne (2009) as well as Galizi (2012). For experiences in the UK, see Burgess (2012).

  51. “We therefore urge ministers to ensure that policy makers are made aware of the evidence that non-regulatory measures are often not likely to be effective if used in isolation and that evidence regarding the whole range of policy interventions should be considered before they commit to using non-regulatory measures alone.” House of Lords (2011), 5.15, p. 36.

  52. On this, see for example Thaler and Sunstein (2008, pp. 240ff.). On the ethical problems of nudging, see also Bovens (2009).

  53. See: Bundestag beschliesst Organspendereform, ZEIT-ONLINE of 25 May 2012. http://www.zeit.de/politik/deutschland/2012-05/organspende-bundestag. June 27, 2012.

  54. On this, see Eurotransplant (2011, p. 36). However, this is true only of those transplantations that are operated via Eurotransplant. Those transplantations that are carried out in the same hospital as where the removal took place are not covered by this statistic. There is, however, no obvious reason that this should largely bias the results.

  55. On this, see for example Abadie and Gay (2006) or Rhitalia et al. (2009).

  56. Due to a big scandal in 2012, the number of transplantations drastically decreased in 2013. Thus, at the moment it is impossible to say whether the new rule will finally increase the number of donations. See: Zahl der Organspender sinkt auf neuen Tiefpunkt, Zeit-Online of January 15, 2014. http://www.zeit.de/gesellschaft/2014-01/organspende-dso-transplantation-zahlen. February 5, 2014.

  57. Though this is hardly a problem of paternalism, because environmental problems, usually caused by external effects, involve third parties. Nevertheless, nudges might be helpful in some cases.

  58. See for this Allcott and Greenstone (2012).

  59. Compared to the traditional bulb, the energy saving bulb had some disadvantages. Thus, in the decision was a trade-off involved.

  60. See Pichert and Katsikopoulos (2008, p. 66).

  61. Sunstein and Reisch (2014, p. 144) admit that nudges do not “stick” when “people have clear preferences that run counter to them.” High costs will usually indorse such “clear preferences”.

  62. Given these costs and taking into account the definition above, this can hardly be qualified as being ‘libertarian’.

  63. Carlin et al. (2013), use similar arguments. In contrast to Schnellenbach (2011, 2012), however, they have no fundamental objections to soft paternalism.

  64. This argument goes back to Buchanan (1954).

  65. See also Rebonato (2012, p. 11; pp. 221ff.).

  66. See, for example, Rizzo and Whiteman (2009a, b, p. 910).

  67. See for example Whitman and Rizzo (2007, pp. 442f.) as well as Rizzo and Whiteman (2009a, pp. 723ff.).

  68. On this, see for example Rizzo and Whiteman (2009a) as well as Whitman and Rizzo (2007).

  69. See for example the critique of model Platonism by Albert (1963).

  70. On this, see Kirchgässner (2010) as well as Pommerehne and Schneider (1985), who showed for the canton Basel-County that, in referenda about the first column of the Swiss old age pension system (AHV), a majority of voters voted in favour of those with low income and against their own material interests.

  71. On this, see Kirchgässner (2008, pp. 154ff.).

  72. It is not the trivial regret at not having been lucky when making a risky decision (investment), that is relevant in this respect, but the consciousness that I should have behaved differently even if I have been lucky and my behaviour did not have negative consequences for me.

  73. If one accepts that the government should take on measures only that lead to a Pareto improvement, then it would also be illegitimate to provide information in order to overcome informational asymmetries or to financially support institutions that provide such information, for example, such as the Stiftung Warentest in Germany. The costs for such activities have to be borne by the taxpayers. Thus, there are citizen who have to pay for these activities but do not benefit. They come into a worse position, which violates the Pareto criterion. On this, see also Marneffe (2006) who believes that it does not make sense with respect to governmental actions always to look for justifications with non-paternalistic arguments, because this sometimes excludes the best arguments for such measures.

  74. On this, see Kirchgässner (1994).

  75. See, for example, Schnellenbach (2011, p. 452).

  76. On this, see the contributions in Constitutional Political Economy 15 (2004), issue 2, in particular the introduction by Brennan (2004).

  77. See also Hausman and Welch (2010, p. 132) who despite being rather reluctant to the use of nudges state: “When choice shaping is not avoidable, then it must be permissible”.

  78. On this, see also Schmidt (1988).

References

  • Abadie, A., & Gay, S. (2006). The impact of presumed consent legislation on cadaveric donation: A cross-country study. Journal of Health Economics, 25, 599–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1963). Modell-Platonismus: Der neoklassische Stil des ökonomischen Denkens in kritischer Beleuchtung. In F. Karrenberg, & H. Albert (Eds.), Sozialwissenschaft und Gesellschaftsgestaltung, Festschrift für Gerhard Weisser (pp. 45–76). Duncker und Humblot, Berlin; reprinted in: Albert, H. (1967). Marktsoziologie und Entscheidungslogik (pp. 331–367). Neuwied/Berlin: Luchterhand.

  • Allcott, H., & Greenstone, M. (2012). Is there an energy efficiency gap? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 26(1), 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andel, N. (1984). Zum Konzept der meritorischen Güter. Finanzarchiv, 42(1984), 630–648.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristoteles, Nicomachean Ethics; English translation: http://www.virtuescience.com/nicomachean-ethics.html.

  • Arneson, R. J. (2005). Joel Feinberg and the justification of hard paternalism. Legal Theory, 11, 259–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, H. (2010). Ist paretianischer Liberalismus doch möglich? Verhaltenswissenschaftliche Ökonomik und Liberaler Paternalismus. List Forum für Wirtschafts- und Finanzpolitik, 36, 43–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. S., & Murphy, K. M. (1988). A theory of rational addiction. Journal of Political Economy, 96, 675–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D., Fradkin, A., & Popov, I. (2011). The welfare economics of default option: A theoretical and empirical analysis of 401(k) plans. NBER Working paper no. 17587, November.

  • Blomquist, S., & Micheletto, L. (2006). Optimal redistributive taxation when government’s and agents’ preferences differ. Journal of Public Economics, 90, 1215–1233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L. (2009). The ethics of nudge. In T. Grüne-Yanoff & S. O. Hansen (Eds.), Preference change: Approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology (pp. 207–219). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G. (2004). An introduction to the status Quo. Constitutional Political Economy, 15, 132–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (1983). Institutional aspects of merit goods analysis. Finanzarchiv N.F., 41, 183–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunello, G., Michaud, P.-C., & Sanz-de-Galdeano, A. (2009). The rise of obesity. Economic Policy, 24, 551–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1954). Individual choice in voting and the market. Journal of Political Economy, 62, 334–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1975). The limits of liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1986). Kommentar. In P. Koslowski (Eds.), Ethik des Kapitalismus (6th ed, 1998, pp. 81–92). Tübingen: Mohr (Siebeck).

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, A. (2012). ‘Nudging’ healthy lifestyles: The UK experiments with the behavioural alternative to regulation and the market. European Journal of Risk Regulation, 1, 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., Issacharoff, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Regulation for conservatives: Behavioral economics and the case for ‘asymmetric paternalism’. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151, 1211–1254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter: Why democracies choose bad policies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlin, B. I., Gervais, S., & Manso, G. (2013). Libertarian paternalism, information production, and financial decision making. Review of Financial Studies, 26, 2204–2228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandon, P., Hutchinson, J. W., Bradlow, E. T., & Young, S. H. (2009). Does in-store marketing work? Effects of the number and position of shelf facing on brand attention and evaluation at the point of purchase. Journal of Marketing, 73, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, J. J., Laibson, D., Madrian, B., & Metrick, A. (2003a). For better or for worse: Default effect and 401(k) savings behavior. In D. Wise (Ed.), Perspectives in the economics of aging (pp. 81–121). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, J. J., Laibson, D., Madrian, B., & Metrick, A. (2003b). Optimal defaults. American Economic Review, 93, 180–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coase, R. H. (1960). The problem of social cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3, 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cutler, D., Deaton, A., & Shapiro, J. M. (2003). Why have Americans become more obese. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 13(3), 93–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Pury, D., Hauser, H., & Schmid, B. (1995). Mut zum Aufbruch: Eine wirtschaftspolitische Agenda für die Schweiz. Zürich: Orell Füssli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dinner, I., Goldstein, D. G., Johnson, E. J., & Liu, K. (2011). Partitioning default effects: Why people choose not to choose. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 17, 332–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, H., Scully, M., & Parkinson, K. (2006). Pester power: Snackfoods displayed at supermarket checkouts in Melbourne, Australia. Health Promotion Journal of Australia, 17, 124–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs, J. S., Loewenstein, G., & Wisdom, J. (2009). Strategies for promoting healthier food choices. American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 99(2), 159–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drèze, X., Hoch, S. J., & Purk, M. E. (1994). Shelf management and space elasticity. Journal of Retailing, 70, 301–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (2005). Moral paternalism. Law and Philosophy, 24, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (2014). Paternalism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paternalism/. January 30, 2015.

  • Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the sirens, studies in rationality and irrationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2000). Ulysses unbound. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eurotransplant International Foundation. (2011). Annual report 2011, Leiden.

  • Feinberg, J. (1986). The moral limits of the criminal law volume 3: Harm to self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., & Pommerehne, W. W. (1990). Public promotion of the arts: A survey of means. Journal of Cultural Economics, 14, 73–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galizi, M. M. (2012). Label, nudge or tax? A review of health policies for risky behaviours. Journal of Public Health Research, 1(e5), 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, D. (1998). Coping rationally with unpreferred preferences. Eastern Economic Journal, 24, 181–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, T., Masur, J. S., & McAdams, R. H. (2013). Libertarian paternalism, path dependence, and temporary law. University of Chicago, public law and legal theory working paper no. 431, June.

  • Glaeser, E. L. (2006). Paternalism and psychology. University of Chicago Law Review, 73, 133–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glod, W. (2008). How not to argue against paternalism. Reason Papers, 30, 7–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J., & Koszegi, B. (2004). Tax incidence when individuals are time-inconsistent: The case of cigarette excise taxation. Journal of Public Economics, 88, 1959–1987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009). Welfare notions for soft paternalism. Papers on economics and evolution no. 0917. Max Planck Institute of Economics, Jena.

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2012). Old wine in New Casks: Libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principle. Social Choice and Welfare, 38, 635–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M., & Welch, B. (2010). Debate: To nudge or not to nudge. Journal of Political Philosophy, 18, 123–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. V. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35, 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. V. (1960). The constitution of liberty. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. v. (1979). Whither democracy. In F. A. v. Hayek (Eds.), Social justice, socialism and democracy: Three australian lectures (pp. 33–45). Sydney: Centre for Independent Studies.

  • Head, J. G. (1966). On merit goods. Finanzarchiv N.F., 25, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, A. O. (1984). Against parsimony: Three easy ways of complicating some categories of economic discourse. American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 74(2), 89–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • House of Lords, Science and Technology Select Committee. (2011). Behaviour Change: 2nd Report of Session 20102012, London.

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1974). Preference among preferences. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, C., & Sunstein, C. R. (2006). Debiasing through law. Journal of Legal Studies, 35, 199–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Just, D. R., & Payne, C. R. (2009). Obesity: Can behavioral economics help? Annals of Behavioral Medicine, 38(Suppl), 47–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaenzig, J., Heinzle, S. L., & Wüstenhagen, R. (2013). Whatever the customer wants, the customer gets? Exploring the gap between consumer preferences and default electricity products in Germany. Energy Policy, 53, 311–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kershnar, S. (2003). A liberal argument for slavery. Journal of Social Philosophy, 34, 510–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (1992). Towards a theory of low-cost decisions. European Journal of Political Economy, 8, 305–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (1994). Constitutional economics and its relevance for the evolution of rules. Kyklos, 47, 321–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (2008). Homo oeconomicus: The economic model of behaviour and its applications to economics and other social sciences. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (2010). On minimal morals. European Journal of Political Economy, 26(2010), 330–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G. (2014). Sanfter Paternalismus, meritorische Güter und der normative Individualismus. List Forum für Wirtschafts- und Finanzpolitik, (Special Issue), 210–238.

  • Kliemt, H. (1986). The veil of insignificance. European Journal of Political Economy, 2, 333–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koch, F. (2000). Der Aufbruch der Pädagogik. Hamburg: Europäische Verlagsanstalt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korman, P., & Prast, H. (2010). What does behavioral economics mean for policy? Challenges for savings and health policies in the Netherlands. De Economist, 158, 101–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kultgen, J. (2014). Professional paternalism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17, 399–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D., Repetto, A., & Tobacman, J. B. (2007). Estimating discount functions with consumption over the lifecycle. NBER working paper no. 13314, August.

  • Leonard, T. C., Besprechung von R. H. Thaler, & C. R. Sunstein (2008). Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 356–360.

  • Loewenstein, G., Brennan, T., & Volpp, K. G. (2007). Asymmetric paternalism to improve health behaviors. Journal of the American Medical Association, 298, 2415–2417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Haisley, E. (2008). The economist as therapist: Methodological ramifications of ‘light paternalism’. In A. Caplin & A. Schotter (Eds.), The foundations of positive and normative economics (pp. 210–245). Oxford et al.: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, G. (2012). Saving smokers from themselves: The paternalistic use of cigarette taxes. University of Cincinnati Law Review, 80, 1–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madrian, B. C., & Shea, D. F. (2001). The power of suggestion: Inertia in 401(k) participation and savings behavior. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 66, 1149–1187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manson, N. C. (2015). Transitional paternalism: How shared normative powers give rise to the asymmetry of adolescent consent and refusal. Bioethics, 29, 66–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marneffe, P. D. (2006). Avoiding paternalism. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 34, 68–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1859). On Liberty. J. W. Parker, London 1859, cited from: M. J. Adler (Ed.), Great books of the world, vol. 40: American state papers, The Federalist, J. S. Mill (1994, pp. 267–323). Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica.

  • Mors, A. (1986). Die Entwicklung der Schulpflicht in Deutschland. Dissertation, Universität Tübingen.

  • Musgrave, R. A. (1957). A multiple theory of budget determination. Finanzarchiv N.F., 17, 333–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, R. A. (1987). Merit Goods. In J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, & P. Newman (Eds.), The new Palgrave: A dictionary of economics (Vol. 3, p. 452f). London/Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Studying optimal paternalism, illustrated by a model of sin taxes. American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 93(2), 186–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2006). Optimal sin taxes. Journal of Public Economics, 90, 1825–1849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philmore, J. (1982). The libertarian case for slavery. The Philosophical Forum, 14(1), 43–58. http://cog.kent.edu/lib/Philmore1/Philmore1.htm. January 3, 2015.

  • Pichert, D., & Katsikopoulos, K. V. (2008). Green defaults: Information presentation and pro-environmental behavior. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 28, 63–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pommerehne, W. W. (1975). Budgetäre Umverteilung in der Demokratie: Ein empirischer Test alternativer Hypothesen. Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften, 95, 327–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pommerehne, W. W., & Schneider, F. (1985). Politisch-ökonomische Überprüfung des Kaufkraftinzidenzkonzepts: Eine Analyse der AHV-Abstimmungen von 1972 und 1978. In E. A. Brugger, & R. L. Frey (Eds.), Sektoralpolitik versus Regionalpolitik, (pp. 75–100). Gruesch: Rüegger.

  • Pope, T. M. (2004). Counting the dragon’s teeth and claws: The definition of hard paternalism. Georgia State University Law Review, 20, 659–722.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pope, T. M. (2005a). Is public health paternalism really never justified? Oklahoma City University Law Review, 30, 121–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pope, T. M. (2005b). Monstrous impersonation: A critique of consent-based justifications for hard paternalism. UMKC Law Review, 73, 681–713.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinet, E. (2004). A meta-analysis of western European external costs estimates. Transportation Research D, 9(2004), 465–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato, R. (2012). Taking liberties: A critical examination of libertarian paternalism. Houndsmill, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato, R. (2013). A critical assessment of libertarian paternalism, mime. Oxford University, October.

  • Rhitalia, A., McDavid, C., Suekarran, S., Myers, L., & Snowdon, A. (2009). Impact of presumed consent for organ donation on donation rates: A systematic review. British Medical Journal, 338, 284–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, M. J., & Whiteman, G. (2009a). The knowledge problem of new paternalism. Brigham Young University Law Review, 20, 905–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, M. J., & Whiteman, G. (2009b). Little brother is watching you: New paternalism on the slippery slope. Arizona Law Review, 51, 685–739.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacha, S. C. (2007). Father knows best: A critique of Joel Feinberg’s soft paternalism. Georgia State University, Philosophy Thesis 17. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1016&context=philosophy_theses.

  • Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status Quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1(1988), 7–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1978). Egonomics, or the art of self-management. American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 68(2), 290–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1980). The intimate contest for self-command. Public Interest, 60, 94–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, K. (1988). Mehr zur Meritorik: Kritisches und Alternatives zu der Lehre von den öffentlichen Gütern. Zeitschrift für Wirtschaft- und Sozialwissenschaften, 108, 383–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnellenbach, J. (2011). Wohlwollendes Anschubsen: Was ist mit liberalem Paternalismus zu erreichen und was sind seine Nebenwirkungen? Perspektiven der Wirtschaftspolitik, 12, 445–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnellenbach, J. (2012). Nudges and norms: On the political economy of soft paternalism. European Journal of Political Economy, 28, 266–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seliger, E., & Whyte, K. P. (2012). Nudging cannot solve complex policy problems. European Journal of Risk Regulation, 1(2012), 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1970). The impossibility of a paretian liberal. Journal of Political Economy, 78, 152–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioural foundations of economic theory. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6, 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2005). Liberalism and paternalism. Legal Theory, 11, 169–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocké, V. (2002). Framing und Rationalität: Die Bedeutung der Informationsdarstellung für das Entscheidungsverhalten. Munich: Oldenbourg.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2008). Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 226–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2014). Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Gaven, London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R., & Reisch, L. A. (2014). Automatically green: Behavioral economics and environmental protection. Harvard Environmental Law Review, 38, 127–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R., & Thaler, R. H. (2003). Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. University of Chicago Law Review, 70, 1159–1202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H. (1992). The winner’s curse, paradoxes and anomalies of economic life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Benartzi, S. (2004). Save more tomorrow: using behavioral economics to increase employee saving. Journal of Political Economy, 112, S164–S187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Shefrin, H. M. (1981). An economic theory of self-control. Journal of Political Economy, 89, 392–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), 93(2), 175–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tietzel, M., & Müller, C. (1998). Noch mehr zur Meritorik. Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- and Sozialwissenschaften, 118, 87–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1987). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. In R. M. Hogarth & M. W. Reder (Eds.), Rational choice: The contrast between economics and psychology (pp. 67–94). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Aaken, A. (2006). Begrenzte Rationalität und Paternalismusgefahr: Das Prinzip des schonendsten Paternalismus. In K. Seelmann, A. Anderheiden, P. Bürkli, M. Hei-nig, & S. Kirste (Eds.), Paternalismus und Recht (pp. 109–144). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, G. (2006). Against the new paternalism: Internalities and the economics of self-control. Policy Analysis No. 563, Cato Institute, 22. February.

  • Whitman, G., & Rizzo, M. J. (2007). Paternalist slopes. New York University Journal of Law and Liberty, 2, 411–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicksell, K. (1896). Über ein neues Prinzip der gerechten Besteuerung. In K. Wicksell (Eds.), Finanztheoretische Untersuchungen (pp. 76–164). Jena: Gustav Fischer; English translation: (1964) A new principle of just taxation. In R. E. Musgrave, & A. T. Peacock (Eds.), Classics in the theory of public finance (pp. 72–118). London: MacMillan.

  • Wisdom, J., Downs, J. S., & Loewenstein, G. (2010). Promoting health choice: Information versus convenience. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 2, 164–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Withers, G. A. (1979). Private demand for public subsidies: An econometric study of cultural support in Australia. Journal of Cultural Economics, 3, 53–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gebhard Kirchgässner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kirchgässner, G. Soft paternalism, merit goods, and normative individualism. Eur J Law Econ 43, 125–152 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-015-9500-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-015-9500-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation