Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2012

01.05.2012 | Scientific Contribution

The desired moral attitude of the physician: (I) empathy

verfasst von: Petra Gelhaus

Erschienen in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Ausgabe 2/2012

Einloggen, um Zugang zu erhalten

Abstract

In professional medical ethics, the physician traditionally is obliged to fulfil specific duties as well as to embody a responsible and trustworthy personality. In the public discussion, different concepts are suggested to describe the desired underlying attitude of physicians. In this article, one of them—empathy—is presented in an interpretation that is meant to depicture (together with the two additional concepts compassion and care) this attitude. Therefore empathy in the clinical context is defined as the adequate understanding of the inner processes of the patient concerning his health-related problems. Adequacy is scrutinized on behalf of the emotional and subjective involvement of he physician, and on the necessary dependence on medical—moral—goals. In the present interpretation, empathy alone is no guarantee of the right moral attitude, but a necessary instrumental skill in order to perceive and treat a patient as an individual person. The concepts of compassion and care that will be discussed in two forthcoming articles are necessary parts to describe the desired moral attitude of the physician more completely.
Fußnoten
1
In the following, I will use the terms „moral“, „good“ (respectively „inherently good“) and „right“ in the meaning of referring to the idea of a special type of normativity that is not easily defined in other terms as it belongs to some basic categories (Moore 1903). Sometimes, „good“ might also appear in the sense of „instrumentally good“ or „useful“. Whenever this happens, it should be clear from the context. I will not take position in these articles between moral objectivism and relativism (though I tend to the first). For my purposes, it suffices to refer to the historical and cultural practice of medicine and its internal values. Like Alasdair MacIntyre (2007), I see however reasons to take medical practice for an excellent example of an objectively good practice. I will not defend that here. Ethics is understood as the philosophy of morals.
 
2
Moral emotions (or sentiments) are a wide field. In this series, I am not dealing with those emotions that refer to moral judgments, such as guilt and remorse, and I abstain from a stance on the role of emotions in ethics in general. I do, however, take position by regarding morals not exclusively as a means to restrict emotions. I take for granted that there are morally adequate emotions, and indeed that it is an impoverished view on ethics reserving it to purely rationalistic judgments.
 
3
In his later work, Slote tries to found morals generally on empathy. That is a very different project from mine (Slote 2007).
 
4
Wilmer emphasizes that this full emotional identification doesn’t imply good understanding: it neglects the unique history and experiences of the other persons. For understanding, the more appropriate way of identification is the empathic “feeling as if I would be he”. (See below).
 
5
That is the reason why physicians are warned to treat close relatives, friends, or even themselves.
 
6
In the concept of empathy in medical practice, the borderline between epistemology and ethics becomes diffuse. Being defined as a mainly (not thoroughly) cognitive way of understanding, empathy appears to be a merely epistemic tool. As a necessary part of medical practice, it is at the same time subjected to moral analysis and judgment.
 
7
The use of the term “feelings” and “emotions” is varying: sometimes they are used synonymously; often feelings are understood as a broader category that includes emotions as specifically directed feelings; or emotions are taken for the objectively observable phenomena of which feelings are the subjective experience (Damasio 1995), etc. For my purposes a clear distinction is not necessary, but as I focus on directed, conscious affective states that can be influenced in a desired way, I usually prefer the term “emotion”, as including the subjective experience of it.
 
8
A thorough deliberation about rational emotions in medical practice can be found in Maier and Shibles (2010), pp. 137–160.
 
9
Howard Spiro illustrates it this way: “We doctors are selected by victories: We reached college because we were bright and competitive in high-school, and we reached medical school through competition and hard-edged achievements. (…) No wonder we have little empathy for the defeated, the humble, the dying, those who have not made it to the top of the heap, and even for the sick.” p. 844.
 
10
Aring is one of the authors who support an attitude of „detached concern“ for doctors; he warns of losing the objectivity and capacity to act by indulging in emotions. Jodie Halpern recommends empathy as a remedy for too much distance which is, according to her, the more common problem of physicians. Nonetheless also Halpern recommends a balance between nearness and distance (Halpern 2001).
 
11
In fact, there is much more for Cassell in understanding the patient as a person than empathy alone. He reminds us of many different aspects in which a person can be inflicted by an illness (Cassell 1982), he emphasizes the meaning of the patient’s narratives and the importance of his values (Cassell 1991). But he always describes the attention to the emotional and subjective side of the patient as competing with the scientific, medical knowledge and technical know-how, and the main task of a physician as a person to unite two opposite poles.
 
12
This goes very well with the current neuropsychological findings about psychopathic delinquents where different brain areas are brought into connection with cognitive and emotional aspects of empathy as a precondition to really understanding the implications of the own deeds for others. (Damasio 1995) In a useful review Grit Hein and Tania Singer summarize: “Accumulating evidence has put forward the view that there are at least two different ways to put us in the shoes (the mind) of the other person. One route is to share the other person’s feelings in an embodied manner, known as empathy (…). The other route is to cognitively infer about the state of the other person, known as ‘theory of mind’, ‘mentalizing’, ‘mind-reading’, or ‘cognitive perspective-taking’. Although often occurring in concert, findings from functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) studies suggest that understanding others on the basis of cognitive perspective taking and empathy recruit different neural networks”. (Hein and Singer 2008, p. 153) Mark that the ‘empathy’ concept in this article is different from our definition which encompasses both emotional as well as cognitive aspects, i.e. the full capacity to “put us in the shoes of another person”. (See also Bauer 2005) In fact the difference between empathy and emotional contagion (which is made by Hein and Singer) is not easily to detect if awareness and cognitive modulation (see Lamm et al. 2007) are taken out of the concept of empathy.
 
13
It is important to keep in mind that this special meaning of empathy is directed on the clinical encounter between physician and patient, in order to safeguard the capacity of the physician to help efficiently and not to lose himself in pity and compassion. In other contexts, the adequate extent of empathy may be much more emotional and nearer to “feeling-with”, of emotional resonance.
 
14
As the psychiatrist deals with very special inner states, namely pathological ones, he also may need a qualitatively different kind of empathy. But the transfer from normal over exceptional to unequivocally sick mental states is even more fluent than in somatic contexts. So the qualitative step in psychiatry might also result from the overlarge quantity. Another example for the context-sensitivity and necessity of empathy is veterinary medicine. Here empathy must work beyond species limits and without help of language. The life of a veterinary surgeon who lacks this capacity is short, and his successes will be few.
 
15
This means in no way that empathy is only an inborn talent that cannot be taught or learned; on the contrary (Platt and Keller 1994). According to Aristotle, virtues that are important elements of character can and should be learned and fostered, and habituation to right behaviour will lead to a better character on the longer run (Aristotle 2002).
 
16
In chapter II of his „Theory of Moral Sentiments“, Adam Smith emphasizes the „pleasures of mutual sympathy“ (sympathy in a meaning very close to contemporary „empathy“). Though at first view it seems to be the sharing of the same emotions, it becomes clearer and clearer that it is the combination of understanding and the kind attitude that is the source of the pleasure (Smith 1759, pp. 12–18).
 
17
„While empathy is believed to have high social value, in actuality it is a neutral human facility whose value is derived from the manner in which it is used“ (Zinn 1993, p. 309).
 
18
In order to be precise, I must admit that it depends on the theory of morality: a strictly consequentialist approach implies that the bad result does make the helpfulness in this case a part of bad agency. But even a consequentialist, if he scrutinises the general attitude of helpfulness, probably would come to the conclusion that, generally, helpfulness leads to morally good results. So it is not the attitude that makes the act of helping bad, and as it normally leads to good consequences, it is rather a good attitude, though it is not decisive for judging the whole act.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat ABIM(American Board of Internal Medicine), ACP-ASIM (American College of Physicians-American Society of Internal Medicine), and European Federation of Internal Medicine. 2002. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physicians’ charter. Lancet 359(9305): 520–522.CrossRef ABIM(American Board of Internal Medicine), ACP-ASIM (American College of Physicians-American Society of Internal Medicine), and European Federation of Internal Medicine. 2002. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physicians’ charter. Lancet 359(9305): 520–522.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Agosta, L. 1984. Empathy and intersubjectivity. In Empathy I, ed. J. Lichtenberg, M. Bornstein, and D. Silver, 43–61. Hillsdal, New Jersey: The Analytic Press. Agosta, L. 1984. Empathy and intersubjectivity. In Empathy I, ed. J. Lichtenberg, M. Bornstein, and D. Silver, 43–61. Hillsdal, New Jersey: The Analytic Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ahlzén, R. 2010. Why should physicians read? Understanding clinical judgement and its relation to literary experience. Karlstad: Faculty of Social and Life sciences. Department of Public Health Science. Ahlzén, R. 2010. Why should physicians read? Understanding clinical judgement and its relation to literary experience. Karlstad: Faculty of Social and Life sciences. Department of Public Health Science.
Zurück zum Zitat Aring, C.D. 1958. Sympathy and empathy. Journal of the American Medical Association 167(4): 448–452.PubMedCrossRef Aring, C.D. 1958. Sympathy and empathy. Journal of the American Medical Association 167(4): 448–452.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Berger, J., and J. Mohr. 1967. A fortunate man. The story of a country doctor. London: The Penguin Press. Berger, J., and J. Mohr. 1967. A fortunate man. The story of a country doctor. London: The Penguin Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Baier, A.C. 2007. Trust, suffering, and the Aesculapian virtues. In Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems, eds. Walker, R.L., Ivanhoe, P.J., 136–153. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Baier, A.C. 2007. Trust, suffering, and the Aesculapian virtues. In Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems, eds. Walker, R.L., Ivanhoe, P.J., 136–153. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bauer, J. 2005. Why I feel what I feel: Intuition and the mystery of the mirror neuron. Hamburg: Hoffmann und Campe Verlag. Bauer, J. 2005. Why I feel what I feel: Intuition and the mystery of the mirror neuron. Hamburg: Hoffmann und Campe Verlag.
Zurück zum Zitat Biller-Andorno, N., Neitzke, G., Frewer, A., Wiesemann, C. 2003. Lehrziele „Medizinethik im Medizinstudium“. Ethik in der Medizin 15(2): S.117–S.121. Biller-Andorno, N., Neitzke, G., Frewer, A., Wiesemann, C. 2003. Lehrziele „Medizinethik im Medizinstudium“. Ethik in der Medizin 15(2): S.117–S.121.
Zurück zum Zitat Cassell, E.J. 1976. The healer’s art. Philadelphia: Lippincott. Cassell, E.J. 1976. The healer’s art. Philadelphia: Lippincott.
Zurück zum Zitat Cassell, E.J. 1982. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. The New England Journal of Medicine 306(11): 639–645.CrossRef Cassell, E.J. 1982. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. The New England Journal of Medicine 306(11): 639–645.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cassell, E.J. 1991. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Cassell, E.J. 1991. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Damasio, A.R. 1995. Descartes error: emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Quill (Harper Collins Publishers). Damasio, A.R. 1995. Descartes error: emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Quill (Harper Collins Publishers).
Zurück zum Zitat Daniels, M.J. 1960. Affect and its control in the medical intern. American Journal of Sociology 66(3): 259–267.CrossRef Daniels, M.J. 1960. Affect and its control in the medical intern. American Journal of Sociology 66(3): 259–267.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat De Sousa, R. 1987. The rationality of emotion. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press. De Sousa, R. 1987. The rationality of emotion. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gelhaus, P. 2011a. Robot decisions. On the importance of virtuous judgment in clinical decision-making. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17(5): 883–887.PubMedCrossRef Gelhaus, P. 2011a. Robot decisions. On the importance of virtuous judgment in clinical decision-making. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17(5): 883–887.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gelhaus, P. 2011b. I, Medical Robot. On the differences between a virtuous doctor and a good robot. International Journal of Person-Centered Medicine 1(2): 301–306. Gelhaus, P. 2011b. I, Medical Robot. On the differences between a virtuous doctor and a good robot. International Journal of Person-Centered Medicine 1(2): 301–306.
Zurück zum Zitat Gilligan, C. 1982. In a different voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gilligan, C. 1982. In a different voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gladstein, G.A. 1983. Understanding empathy: Integrating counseling, developmental, and social psychology perspectives. Journal of Counseling Psychology 30(4): 467–482.CrossRef Gladstein, G.A. 1983. Understanding empathy: Integrating counseling, developmental, and social psychology perspectives. Journal of Counseling Psychology 30(4): 467–482.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Halpern, J. 2001. From detached concern to empathy. Humanizing medical practice. New York: Oxford University Press. Halpern, J. 2001. From detached concern to empathy. Humanizing medical practice. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hein, G., and T. Singer. 2008. I feel how you feel but not always: the empathic brain and its modulation. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 18: 153–158.PubMedCrossRef Hein, G., and T. Singer. 2008. I feel how you feel but not always: the empathic brain and its modulation. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 18: 153–158.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hoffman, M.L. 2000. Empathy and moral development. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hoffman, M.L. 2000. Empathy and moral development. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Katz, R.L. 1963. Empathy: its nature and uses. New York: Free Press of Glencoe. Katz, R.L. 1963. Empathy: its nature and uses. New York: Free Press of Glencoe.
Zurück zum Zitat Kohlberg, L., C. Levine, and A. Hewer. 1983. Moral stages: A current formulation and a response to critics. Basel, NY: Karger. Kohlberg, L., C. Levine, and A. Hewer. 1983. Moral stages: A current formulation and a response to critics. Basel, NY: Karger.
Zurück zum Zitat Lamm, C., C.D. Batson, and J. Decety. 2007. The neural substrate of human empathy: Effects of perspective-taking and cognitive appraisal. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19(1): 42–58.PubMedCrossRef Lamm, C., C.D. Batson, and J. Decety. 2007. The neural substrate of human empathy: Effects of perspective-taking and cognitive appraisal. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19(1): 42–58.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat MacIntyre, A. 2007. After virtue, 3rd ed. London: Duckworth. MacIntyre, A. 2007. After virtue, 3rd ed. London: Duckworth.
Zurück zum Zitat Maier, B., and W.A. Shibles. 2010. The philosophy and practice of medicine and bioethics: A naturalistic/humanistic approach. New York: Springer. Maier, B., and W.A. Shibles. 2010. The philosophy and practice of medicine and bioethics: A naturalistic/humanistic approach. New York: Springer.
Zurück zum Zitat Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Olinick, S.L. 1987. A critique of empathy and sympathy. In Empathy I, ed. J. Lichtenberg, M. Bornstein, and D. Silver, 137–166. Hillsdal, New Jersey: The Analytic Press. Olinick, S.L. 1987. A critique of empathy and sympathy. In Empathy I, ed. J. Lichtenberg, M. Bornstein, and D. Silver, 137–166. Hillsdal, New Jersey: The Analytic Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Parsons, T. 1991. The social system, 2nd ed. London: Routledge. Parsons, T. 1991. The social system, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Pedersen, R. 2008. Empathy: A wolf in sheep’s clothing? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11(3): 325–335.CrossRef Pedersen, R. 2008. Empathy: A wolf in sheep’s clothing? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11(3): 325–335.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pellegrino, E.D. 2007. Professing medicine, virtue based ethics, and the retrieval of professionalism. In Working virtue: virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems, ed. R.L. Walker, and P.J. Ivanhoe, 61–85. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Pellegrino, E.D. 2007. Professing medicine, virtue based ethics, and the retrieval of professionalism. In Working virtue: virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems, ed. R.L. Walker, and P.J. Ivanhoe, 61–85. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Pellegrino, E.D. 1995. Toward a virtue-based normative ethics for the health professions. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5(3): 263–277. Pellegrino, E.D. 1995. Toward a virtue-based normative ethics for the health professions. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5(3): 263–277.
Zurück zum Zitat Pellegrino, E.D., and D.C. Thomasma. 1988. For the patient’s good The restoration of beneficence in health care. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Pellegrino, E.D., and D.C. Thomasma. 1988. For the patient’s good The restoration of beneficence in health care. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Platt, F.W., and V.F. Keller. 1994. Empathic communication. A teachable and learnable skill. Journal of General Internal Medicine 9(4): 222–226.PubMedCrossRef Platt, F.W., and V.F. Keller. 1994. Empathic communication. A teachable and learnable skill. Journal of General Internal Medicine 9(4): 222–226.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rudebeck, C.E. 1992. General practice and the dialogue of clinical practice. On symptoms, symptom presentations and bodily empathy. Scandinavian Journal of Primary Healthcare 10(suppl. 1):1–87. Rudebeck, C.E. 1992. General practice and the dialogue of clinical practice. On symptoms, symptom presentations and bodily empathy. Scandinavian Journal of Primary Healthcare 10(suppl. 1):1–87.
Zurück zum Zitat Rushton, J.P. 1980. Altruism, socialisation, and society. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Rushton, J.P. 1980. Altruism, socialisation, and society. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Zurück zum Zitat Sherman, N. 2005. Stoic warriors: The ancient philosophy behind the military mind. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Sherman, N. 2005. Stoic warriors: The ancient philosophy behind the military mind. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Slote, M. 2001. Morals from motives. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Slote, M. 2001. Morals from motives. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Slote, M. 2007. The ethics of care and empathy. New York: Routledge. Slote, M. 2007. The ethics of care and empathy. New York: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Smith, A. 1759. The theory of moral sentiments. London: Millar. Smith, A. 1759. The theory of moral sentiments. London: Millar.
Zurück zum Zitat Solomon, R.C. 2006. True to our feelings: What our emotions are really telling us. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Solomon, R.C. 2006. True to our feelings: What our emotions are really telling us. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Spiro, H. 1992. What is empathy and can it be taught? Annals of Internal Medicine 116(10): 843–846.PubMed Spiro, H. 1992. What is empathy and can it be taught? Annals of Internal Medicine 116(10): 843–846.PubMed
Zurück zum Zitat Wilmer, H.A. 1968. The doctor-patient relationship and the issues of pity, sympathy and empathy. The British Journal of Medical Psychology 41(3): 243–248.PubMedCrossRef Wilmer, H.A. 1968. The doctor-patient relationship and the issues of pity, sympathy and empathy. The British Journal of Medical Psychology 41(3): 243–248.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Zahavi, D. 2001. Beyond empathy. Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 151–167. Zahavi, D. 2001. Beyond empathy. Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 151–167.
Metadaten
Titel
The desired moral attitude of the physician: (I) empathy
verfasst von
Petra Gelhaus
Publikationsdatum
01.05.2012
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Ausgabe 2/2012
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-011-9366-4

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2012

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2/2012 Zur Ausgabe

Short Literarture Notices

Short literature notices