Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3/2013

01.08.2013 | Scientific Contribution

The right perspective on responsibility for ill health

verfasst von: Karl Persson

Erschienen in: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy | Ausgabe 3/2013

Einloggen, um Zugang zu erhalten

Abstract

There is a growing trend in policy making of holding people responsible for their lifestyle-based diseases. This has sparked a heated debate on whether people are responsible for these illnesses, which has now come to an impasse. In this paper, I present a psychological model that explains why different views on people’s responsibility for their health exist and how we can reach a resolution of the disagreement. My conclusion is that policymakers should not perceive people as responsible while health care personnel should take the opposing view.
Fußnoten
1
Lie and Sabik (2008), Schmidt et al. (2009), Schmidt (2009a, b). For references to the general discussion about the movement toward what is sometimes called “conditional welfare regimes” in Europe and North America, see Knight and Stemplowska (2011), n. 2.
 
2
For philosophers, see for example Rakowski (1991), Scruton (2000), Segall (2009), Walker (2010). For non-philosophers, see for example Williams (1992), SOU (1995, p. 5, 97f), Bråkenhielm (1990), Bowling (1996), Dolan et al. (1999). Many of these, however, would be hesitant to withhold recourses if there was enough for everyone (see for example Walker 2010 and SOU 1995:5) which makes it plausible that one reason for why it has grown large in recent years is the perceived lack of recourses.
 
3
Refer to Segall (2009) and Sharkey and Gillam (2010) for recent overviews of the debate. For a historical perspective, see Resier (1985).
 
4
Some argue that we have no reason to hold people responsible for their ill health even when they are responsible for it (Harris 1995; Wikler 2002). Even though this is an interesting question, I will not pursue it here.
 
5
There are at least three reasons often combined in the debate. Except for the argument I present above, there are reasons to believe that our actions do not cause ill health even when we suffer from “lifestyle-based” diseases, even when these actions cause ill health, and when such behaviors stem from addiction.
 
6
See for example Minkler (1999): 126–130, Daniels (2008): 156 and Buyx (2008): 872.
 
7
For a recent substantial and critical overview of the different arguments, see Haji (2009). There have been concerns over whether this experiment actually succeeds in showing that non-philosophers are incompatibilists under these conditions instead of fatalists, which pertains to the notion that whatever we do, the outcome remains the same. Other similar descriptions, which have contributed to these worries, have, however, revealed similar results (Nahmias et al. 2007, p. 227). I have also argued elsewhere that we, at least for now, do not have any decisive reasons to believe that fatalism causes people to think the way they do when confronted with these scenarios (Björnsson and Persson 2012 ).
 
8
The careful reader has probably noticed that I do not speak of “free will” anywhere. This is due to the fact that many philosophers today believe that we can, in a substantial sense, be responsible even if we do not have free will (e.g. Fischer and Ravizza 1998).
 
9
For example, during the evaluation of whether Bill (who killed his wife and children to be with his secretary) was responsible for his act, 72 % answered yes even though his action was determined by factors outside his control (Nichols and Knobe 2007, p. 670). This finding is also supported by other similar studies (Nahmias et al. 2007).
 
10
I say this even though I have argued for a compatibilist position elsewhere (Björnsson and Persson 2012). My argument for this position, however, is made on the grounds of the psychological model below.
 
11
However, refer to Duus-Otterström (2008) for a different view. I have argued elsewhere that this is erroneous (Persson 2008, 2009).
 
12
The model, then, is only meant to capture many people’s intuitions about these cases, not everyones. Furthermore, it is not a normative or social theory, it is simply a hypothesis about how and why we judge the way we do when confronted with certain cases.
 
13
For a more thorough explanation, see Björnsson and Persson (2012).
 
14
For a more substantial discussion about what they call reason-responsiveness, see Fischer and Ravizza (1998).
 
15
A large body of evidence supports EH. Together with Björnsson, I have argued that EH can account for the dynamics in the philosophical discussions on moral luck, heteronomy, and a wide variety of ordinary judgments of responsibility Björnsson and Persson (2012). We have also argued that EH can account for a range of perplexing and diverging intuitions among non-philosophers, as revealed by recent experimental philosophy (Björnsson and Persson forthcoming). Björnsson (2011) has also argued that EH can account for the different types of intuitions that we have about collective responsibility.
 
16
Since what we perceive as an explanation is relative to our underlying normative expectations, we might think that the explanation for why the house burned down is the omission to extinguish the fire even though they have not got paid. For example, we might think that people who are firemen always have an obligation to extinguish fires, even in these sorts of cases. If this is true, then we would still think that the explanation for why the house burned down lies in the firemen’s inaction. But those of us who believe that firemen, as everyone else, only are obliged to do their job when their employee fulfills their end, the explanation for why the house burned down is that the employer did not fulfill their end of the bargain.
 
17
That different explanatory perspectives have this sort of influence on our explanatory judgments is well known and has been discussed in relation to law (Hart and Honoré 1986) and epidemiology (Holland 2007). However, before Björnsson and Persson (2012), it has not been used in a systematic way to analyze either the responsibility debate in general or the debate concerning personal responsibility for health.
 
18
In the case of smoking, this might not be true because it is often argued that people are manipulated. I am going to set that aside and assume that they are not.
 
19
I am not going to discuss the matter of distributing organs because this topic is much more of a micro-level question.
 
20
Questions about autonomy are also on the rise in these contexts (Munthe 2008). I discuss the implications of these views under the next heading. But for the short term, if someone believes that autonomy has a greater value than the others discussed in this section, then the argument in favor of the policymaker taking a perspective in which they perceive people as excused, fails.
 
21
For a defense of utilitarianism, see Sidgwick (1907) or Tännsjö (1998). A wide range of different utilitarian theories are available, from rule utilitarianism to aim-based utilitarianism. Different values for the promotion of utilitarianism have also been discussed and defended.
 
22
Utilitarianism and cost-effectiveness are, of course, not one and the same thing. Strictly speaking, if utilitarianism is true, I believe determining the course of action would be impossible to accomplish in practice (Gren 2004). My use of “utilitarianism” is instead similar to how people often use it in contexts wherein priority setting and other similar questions are discussed.
 
23
See Roberts (2006, p. 56) for a similar view.
 
24
See for example Crawford (1977) and Wilkinson (2005).
 
25
Fierlbeck (1996) explains his results in the same way. Conservatives are less interested in preventive work because they believe that people are responsible for their ill health.
 
26
Less preventive work may, of course, lead to greater happiness than can alternatives given that health is not all that matters and different types of infringements on people’s autonomy may diminish well-being even though better health is achieved (cf. Mill 1869). However, taking an abstract perspective that disallows these types of considerations has not been discussed.
 
27
I am not claiming here, of course, that they know about the psychological model presented in this paper. Instead, I believe that at least some of the people who were employed in the project had an intuitive feeling about how to approach encouraging the judgment of ordinary people as blameless. I think this made them even more adamant about adopting a clear stance on motivational structures having no role in explaining why one group fared better than another.
 
28
Cf. Björnsson and Persson (2012).
 
29
Parfit (1991, 1997), Temkin (1993). There are also different kinds of “threshold views,” or “sufficiency views,” which state that when people have reached a certain threshold, further improvements are not required on account of justice. For a classic defense, see Frankfurt (1971) and for a recent overview and critique, refer to Casal (2007).
 
30
We can distribute health as well as health care. For a discussion, see Daniels (2008, pp. 29–102) or Segall (2009).
 
31
An opportunity-based egalitarian should opt for the same perspective. Many such egalitarians, such as Norman Daniels (2008), often argue that good health is special compared with other beneficial attributes because it is instrumental in affording us opportunities to realize our life goals (pp. 29–79). Suffering from ill health deprives us of the opportunities available to others who are healthy, which is unfair from the opportunity-based egalitarian view. Given that my empirical arguments are sound, perceiving people as responsible for ill health may lead to a low motivation to help those with poor health and eradicate the social determinants of ill health. This situation naturally provides purely opportunity-based egalitarians a strong argument against adopting such a perspective. The same line of reasoning, as I said at the end of the former paragraph, can be applied to the other egalitarian views as well.
 
32
Beauchamp and Childress (2008). It might be argued, of course, that we should use the same ethical considerations on both levels. I am not going to discuss this here, however, since it would take us too far afield.
 
33
Numerous studies have been made on the negative attitudes that many doctors hold toward people who suffer from lifestyle-based diseases, such as obesity. I discuss this in the next paragraph.
 
34
Strictly speaking, Alfred Mele is not defending a sufficient condition, but only a necessary condition for autonomy. It should also be noted that there is and has been a huge discussion about what autonomy is and how it should be defended [e.g. Kant (1785), Mill (1869), Korsgaard (1996), Scanlon (1998)].
 
35
This is, of course, an oversimplification on my part. For a discussion about how different types of perspectives on autonomy may be used to justify varied treatment approaches, see Sandman and Munthe (2009).
 
36
Kuokkanen and Leino-Kilpi (2000). A recent study revealed, for instance, that when patients feel that they are treated with respect (a phenomenon presumably more common when patients are considered accountable), they feel more able to go back to work (Lynöe et al. 2011).
 
37
In debates, people often distinguish between paternalism, shared decision making, and informed choice (Charles et al. 1997). Paternalistic decision making is the classic authoritarian approach in which a doctor basically decides what should be done. Informed choice is at the other end of the spectrum, in which a doctor withdraws from the decision-making process and only provides a patient with information about his/her condition and different ways to treat it. Shared decision making is a situation wherein a patient is involved in the decision-making process but the doctor does not completely withdraw from it by only giving information. Both parties are involved, discussing what decision the patient should make.
 
38
For a review, see for example Rodriguez-Osorio (2008).
 
39
One problem with taking the concrete perspective, however, is that doctors might view obesity, for instance, as not a disease and therefore does not require involvement (Hansson et al. 2011). I believe that this problem can be solved through specificity. Being obese in itself is not a kind of illness; rather, the consequences that stem from it, such as heart disease and diabetes, are. For a different opinion, see WHO (2000).
 
40
For a discussion about blaming patients, see for example Martin (2001).
 
41
I would like to hint at a problem that may be worth looking into. According to recent studies, helping people with their lifestyle-based diseases can be stressful for health care personnel given that they often do not see any behavioral changes among patients (Jallinoja et al. 2007). This type of stress can have negative effects on the health of personnel, which is important in its own right. However, (and perhaps more important), when these health care providers are emphasized, they are more likely to hold stereotypes about patients, which can generate negative results [for a classical monograph in this area, see Michael Lipsky’s Street-level Bureaucracy; Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Services (1980)]. I do not pursue the matter further here because it would lend more speculativeness to the other ideas that I have discussed in this section. More research is needed to definitively discuss the subject.
 
42
This is actually compatible with EH; see Björnsson and Persson (2012).
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Arneson, R.J. 1989. Equality and equal opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies 56: 77–93.CrossRef Arneson, R.J. 1989. Equality and equal opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies 56: 77–93.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Arpaly, N. 2003. Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford U P. Arpaly, N. 2003. Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2008. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: Oxford U P. Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2008. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Bellas, P.A., S.M. Asch, and M. Wilkes. 2000. What students bring to medical school attitude of health personnel, health promotion, preventive medicine, undergraduate medical education? American Journal of Preventive Medicine 18(3): 242–248.PubMedCrossRef Bellas, P.A., S.M. Asch, and M. Wilkes. 2000. What students bring to medical school attitude of health personnel, health promotion, preventive medicine, undergraduate medical education? American Journal of Preventive Medicine 18(3): 242–248.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Björnsson, G. 2011. Joint responsibility without individual control: Applying the explanation Hypothesis. In Compatibilist Responsibility: beyond free will and determinism, eds. J. van den Hoven, I. van de Poel & N. Vincent. Springer. Björnsson, G. 2011. Joint responsibility without individual control: Applying the explanation Hypothesis. In Compatibilist Responsibility: beyond free will and determinism, eds. J. van den Hoven, I. van de Poel & N. Vincent. Springer.
Zurück zum Zitat Björnsson, G., and K. Persson. 2012. The Explanatory Component of Moral Responsibility. Noûs 46(2): 326–354 Björnsson, G., and K. Persson. 2012. The Explanatory Component of Moral Responsibility. Noûs 46(2): 326–354
Zurück zum Zitat Björnsson, G., and K. Persson. Forthcoming. A unified Empirical Account of responsibility judgments. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Björnsson, G., and K. Persson. Forthcoming. A unified Empirical Account of responsibility judgments. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
Zurück zum Zitat Bowling, A. 1996. Health care rationing: The public debate. British Medical Journal 312: 670–674.PubMedCrossRef Bowling, A. 1996. Health care rationing: The public debate. British Medical Journal 312: 670–674.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bråkenhielm, C.R. 1990. Health care on equal terms (Vård på lika villkor) in the cost of health care (Vårdens pris). Stockholm: Verbum Förlag. Bråkenhielm, C.R. 1990. Health care on equal terms (Vård på lika villkor) in the cost of health care (Vårdens pris). Stockholm: Verbum Förlag.
Zurück zum Zitat Buyx, A.M. 2008. Personal responsibility for health as a rationing criterion: Why we don’t like it and why maybe we should? Journal of Medical Ethics 34: 871–874.PubMedCrossRef Buyx, A.M. 2008. Personal responsibility for health as a rationing criterion: Why we don’t like it and why maybe we should? Journal of Medical Ethics 34: 871–874.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Charles, C., A. Gafni, and T. Whelan. 1997. Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: What does it mean? (or it takes at least two to tango). Social Science and Medicine 44(5): 681–692.PubMedCrossRef Charles, C., A. Gafni, and T. Whelan. 1997. Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: What does it mean? (or it takes at least two to tango). Social Science and Medicine 44(5): 681–692.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chisholm, R. 2003. Human freedom and the self. In Free will, ed. M. Broukal, and G. Watson, 26–38. Oxford: Oxford U P. Chisholm, R. 2003. Human freedom and the self. In Free will, ed. M. Broukal, and G. Watson, 26–38. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Clarke, R. 2003. Libertarian Accounts of Free Will. New York: Oxford U P. Clarke, R. 2003. Libertarian Accounts of Free Will. New York: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Cohen, G.A. 1989. On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99: 906–944.CrossRef Cohen, G.A. 1989. On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99: 906–944.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Crawford, R. 1977. You are dangerous to your health: The ideology and politics of victim blaming. International Journal of Health Services 7(4): 663–680.PubMedCrossRef Crawford, R. 1977. You are dangerous to your health: The ideology and politics of victim blaming. International Journal of Health Services 7(4): 663–680.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Daniels, N. 2008. Just health—Meeting the needs fairly. New York: Cambridge U P. Daniels, N. 2008. Just health—Meeting the needs fairly. New York: Cambridge U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Daníelsdóttir, S., K.S. O’Brien, and A. Ciao. 2010. Anti-fat prejudice reduction: A review of published studies. Obesity Facts 3: 47–58.PubMedCrossRef Daníelsdóttir, S., K.S. O’Brien, and A. Ciao. 2010. Anti-fat prejudice reduction: A review of published studies. Obesity Facts 3: 47–58.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Oxford: Oxford U P. Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Dolan, P., R. Cookson, and B. Ferguson. 1999. Effect of discussion and deliberation on the public’s view of priority setting in health care: Focus group study. British Medical Journal 318: 916–919.PubMedCrossRef Dolan, P., R. Cookson, and B. Ferguson. 1999. Effect of discussion and deliberation on the public’s view of priority setting in health care: Focus group study. British Medical Journal 318: 916–919.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Duus-Otterström, G. 2008. Betting against hard determinism. Research Publica 14: 219–235.CrossRef Duus-Otterström, G. 2008. Betting against hard determinism. Research Publica 14: 219–235.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Duus-Otterström, G. 2011. Freedom of will and the value of choice. Social Theory and Practice 37: 256–284.CrossRef Duus-Otterström, G. 2011. Freedom of will and the value of choice. Social Theory and Practice 37: 256–284.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dworkin, R. 1981. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: 283–345. Dworkin, R. 1981. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: 283–345.
Zurück zum Zitat Fallowfield, L.J., A. Hall, P. Maguire, M. Baum, and R.P. A’Hern. 1994. Psychological effects of being offered choice of surgery for breast cancer. British Medical Journal 309: 448.PubMedCrossRef Fallowfield, L.J., A. Hall, P. Maguire, M. Baum, and R.P. A’Hern. 1994. Psychological effects of being offered choice of surgery for breast cancer. British Medical Journal 309: 448.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fierlbeck, K. 1996. Policy and ideology: The politics of post-reform health policy in the United Kingdom. International Journal of Health Services 26: 529–546.PubMedCrossRef Fierlbeck, K. 1996. Policy and ideology: The politics of post-reform health policy in the United Kingdom. International Journal of Health Services 26: 529–546.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fischer, J., and M. Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge U. P. Fischer, J., and M. Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge U. P.
Zurück zum Zitat Foster, G.D., T.A. Wadden, A.P. Makris, D. Davidson, R.S. Sanderson, D.B. Allison, and A. Kessler. 2003. Primary care physicians’ attitudes about obesity and its treatment. Obesity Research 11: 1168–1177.PubMedCrossRef Foster, G.D., T.A. Wadden, A.P. Makris, D. Davidson, R.S. Sanderson, D.B. Allison, and A. Kessler. 2003. Primary care physicians’ attitudes about obesity and its treatment. Obesity Research 11: 1168–1177.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Frankfurt, H. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68(1): 5–20.CrossRef Frankfurt, H. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68(1): 5–20.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gorter, K.J., G.J. Tuytel, R.R. de Leeuw, J.M. Bensing, and G. Rutten. 2011. Opinions of patients with type 2 diabetes about responsibility, setting targets and willingness to take medication. A cross-sectional survey. Patient Perception, Preference and Participation 84: 56–61. Gorter, K.J., G.J. Tuytel, R.R. de Leeuw, J.M. Bensing, and G. Rutten. 2011. Opinions of patients with type 2 diabetes about responsibility, setting targets and willingness to take medication. A cross-sectional survey. Patient Perception, Preference and Participation 84: 56–61.
Zurück zum Zitat Gren, J. 2004. Applying utilitarianism—The problem of practical action-guidance. Göteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgenes. Gren, J. 2004. Applying utilitarianism—The problem of practical action-guidance. Göteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgenes.
Zurück zum Zitat Haji, I. 2009. Incompatibilism’s allure: Principal arguments for incompatibilism. Peterborough: Broadview Press. Haji, I. 2009. Incompatibilism’s allure: Principal arguments for incompatibilism. Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Harris, J. 1995. Could we hold people responsible for their own adverse health? Journal of contemporary health law and policy 147: 147–153. Harris, J. 1995. Could we hold people responsible for their own adverse health? Journal of contemporary health law and policy 147: 147–153.
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, H.L.A., and T. Honoré. 1986. Causation in the law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon. Hart, H.L.A., and T. Honoré. 1986. Causation in the law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.
Zurück zum Zitat Heisler, M., D.M. Smith, R.A. Hayward, S.L. Krein, and E.A. Kerr. 2003. How well do patients’ assessments of their diabetes self-management correlate with actual glycemic control and receipt of recommended diabetes services? Diabetes Care 26: 738–743.PubMedCrossRef Heisler, M., D.M. Smith, R.A. Hayward, S.L. Krein, and E.A. Kerr. 2003. How well do patients’ assessments of their diabetes self-management correlate with actual glycemic control and receipt of recommended diabetes services? Diabetes Care 26: 738–743.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Holland, S. 2007. Public health ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press. Holland, S. 2007. Public health ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Jallinoja, P., P. Absetz, R. Kuronen, A. Nissinen, M. Talja, A. Uutela, and K. Patja. 2007. The dilemma of patient responsibility for lifestyle change: Perceptions among primary care physicians and nurses. Scandinavian Journal of Primary Health Care 25: 244–249.PubMedCrossRef Jallinoja, P., P. Absetz, R. Kuronen, A. Nissinen, M. Talja, A. Uutela, and K. Patja. 2007. The dilemma of patient responsibility for lifestyle change: Perceptions among primary care physicians and nurses. Scandinavian Journal of Primary Health Care 25: 244–249.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kane, R. 1996. The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford U P. Kane, R. 1996. The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Kant, I. 1785 [2008]. The groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Radford, VA: Wilder. Kant, I. 1785 [2008]. The groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Radford, VA: Wilder.
Zurück zum Zitat Kaplan, S., S. Greenfield, and J.E. Ware. 1989. Assessing the effects of physician–patient interactions on the outcomes of chronic disease. Medical Care 27: 110–127.CrossRef Kaplan, S., S. Greenfield, and J.E. Ware. 1989. Assessing the effects of physician–patient interactions on the outcomes of chronic disease. Medical Care 27: 110–127.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Knight, C. 2009a. Luck egalitarianism: Equality, responsibility, and justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P. Knight, C. 2009a. Luck egalitarianism: Equality, responsibility, and justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Knight, C. 2009b. Luck egalitarianism: Equality, responsibility and justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P. Knight, C. 2009b. Luck egalitarianism: Equality, responsibility and justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Knight, C., and Z. Stemplowska. 2011. Responsibility and respect: Reconciling to egalitarian visions. In Knight and Stemplowska responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford: Oxford U P. Knight, C., and Z. Stemplowska. 2011. Responsibility and respect: Reconciling to egalitarian visions. In Knight and Stemplowska responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Korsgaard, C. 1996. Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge U P.CrossRef Korsgaard, C. 1996. Creating the kingdom of ends. Cambridge: Cambridge U P.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kuokkanen, L., and H. Leino-Kilpi. 2000. Power and empowerment in nursing: Three theoretical approaches. Journal of Advanced Nursing 31: 235–241.PubMedCrossRef Kuokkanen, L., and H. Leino-Kilpi. 2000. Power and empowerment in nursing: Three theoretical approaches. Journal of Advanced Nursing 31: 235–241.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lie, L.M., and R.K. Sabik. 2008. Priority setting in health care: Lessons from the experiences of eight countries. International Journal for Equity in Health 7(4): 1–13. Lie, L.M., and R.K. Sabik. 2008. Priority setting in health care: Lessons from the experiences of eight countries. International Journal for Equity in Health 7(4): 1–13.
Zurück zum Zitat Lipsky, M. 1980. Street level bureaucrats. New York: The Russell Sage Foundation. Lipsky, M. 1980. Street level bureaucrats. New York: The Russell Sage Foundation.
Zurück zum Zitat Manning, D.L., and C. Dickens. 2006. Health literacy: More choice, but do cancer patients have the skills to decide? European Journal of Cancer Care 15: 448–452. Manning, D.L., and C. Dickens. 2006. Health literacy: More choice, but do cancer patients have the skills to decide? European Journal of Cancer Care 15: 448–452.
Zurück zum Zitat Lynöe N., M. Wessell, D. Olsson, K. Alexanderson, and Helgesson G. 2011. Respectful encounters and return to work: empirical study of long-term sick-listed patients' experiences of Swedish healthcare. BMJ Open 2011(1): e000246. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2011-000246. Lynöe N., M. Wessell, D. Olsson, K. Alexanderson, and Helgesson G. 2011. Respectful encounters and return to work: empirical study of long-term sick-listed patients' experiences of Swedish healthcare. BMJ Open 2011(1): e000246. doi:​10.​1136/​bmjopen-2011-000246.
Zurück zum Zitat Marmot, M. 2004. The status syndrome—How social standing affects our health and longevity? New York: Henry Holt and Company. Marmot, M. 2004. The status syndrome—How social standing affects our health and longevity? New York: Henry Holt and Company.
Zurück zum Zitat Martin, M. 2001. Responsibility for health and blaming victims. Journal of Medical Humanities 22(2): 95–114.CrossRef Martin, M. 2001. Responsibility for health and blaming victims. Journal of Medical Humanities 22(2): 95–114.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mele, A. 1995. Autonomous agents: From self control to autonomy. New York: Oxford U P. Mele, A. 1995. Autonomous agents: From self control to autonomy. New York: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Mill, J.S. 1869. On liberty. London: Longman, Roberts & Green. Mill, J.S. 1869. On liberty. London: Longman, Roberts & Green.
Zurück zum Zitat Minkler, M. 1999. Personal responsibility for health? A review of the arguments and the evidence at century’s end. Health Education & Behavior 26: 121–141.CrossRef Minkler, M. 1999. Personal responsibility for health? A review of the arguments and the evidence at century’s end. Health Education & Behavior 26: 121–141.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Munthe, C. 2008. The goals of public health: An integrated, multidimensional model. Public Health Ethics 1(1): 39–52.CrossRef Munthe, C. 2008. The goals of public health: An integrated, multidimensional model. Public Health Ethics 1(1): 39–52.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Murray E., L. Pollack, M. White, and B. Lo. 2007. Clinical decision-making: Patients' preferences and experiences. Patient Education and Counseling 65(2): 189–196. Murray E., L. Pollack, M. White, and B. Lo. 2007. Clinical decision-making: Patients' preferences and experiences. Patient Education and Counseling 65(2): 189–196.
Zurück zum Zitat Nahmias, E., J. Coates, and T. Kvaran. 2007. Free will, moral responsibility, and mechanism: Experiments on folk intuitions. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 214–242.CrossRef Nahmias, E., J. Coates, and T. Kvaran. 2007. Free will, moral responsibility, and mechanism: Experiments on folk intuitions. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 214–242.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nichols, S., and J. Knobe. 2007. Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs 41(4): 663–685.CrossRef Nichols, S., and J. Knobe. 2007. Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs 41(4): 663–685.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat O’Connor, T. 2000. Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Oxford U P. O’Connor, T. 2000. Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat O’Brien, K.S., R.M. Puhl, J.D. Latner, A.S. Mir, and J.H. Hunter. 2010. Reducing anti-fat prejudice in preservice health students: A randomized trial. Obesity 18(11): 2138–2144.PubMedCrossRef O’Brien, K.S., R.M. Puhl, J.D. Latner, A.S. Mir, and J.H. Hunter. 2010. Reducing anti-fat prejudice in preservice health students: A randomized trial. Obesity 18(11): 2138–2144.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Parfit, D. 1991. Equality or priority?, 1–42. The Lindley Lecture: University of Kansas Press. Parfit, D. 1991. Equality or priority?, 1–42. The Lindley Lecture: University of Kansas Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Pereboom, D. 2001. Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge U P.CrossRef Pereboom, D. 2001. Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge U P.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Persson, K. 2008. Förtjänstbaserade straff -något att satsa på? (Should we bet on desert based punishment?). Tidskrift för politisk filosofi (Journal of Political Philosophy) 3: 10. Persson, K. 2008. Förtjänstbaserade straff -något att satsa på? (Should we bet on desert based punishment?). Tidskrift för politisk filosofi (Journal of Political Philosophy) 3: 10.
Zurück zum Zitat Persson, K. 2009. En sista satsning: svar till Göran Duus-Otterström. (A last bet: an answer to Göran Duus-Otterström). Tidskrift för politisk filosofi (Journal of Political Philosophy) 1: 62–64. Persson, K. 2009. En sista satsning: svar till Göran Duus-Otterström. (A last bet: an answer to Göran Duus-Otterström). Tidskrift för politisk filosofi (Journal of Political Philosophy) 1: 62–64.
Zurück zum Zitat Prop. 1996/1997:60. Priority setting in health care (Prioriteringar inom hälso-och sjukvården). Prop. 1996/1997:60. Priority setting in health care (Prioriteringar inom hälso-och sjukvården).
Zurück zum Zitat Puhl, R.M., and K.D. Brownell. 2001. Bias, discrimination, and obesity. Obesity Research 9: 788–905.PubMedCrossRef Puhl, R.M., and K.D. Brownell. 2001. Bias, discrimination, and obesity. Obesity Research 9: 788–905.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Puhl, R.M., and K.D. Brownell. 2006. Confronting and coping with weight stigma: An investigation of overweight and obese adults. Obesity 14: 1802–1815.PubMedCrossRef Puhl, R.M., and K.D. Brownell. 2006. Confronting and coping with weight stigma: An investigation of overweight and obese adults. Obesity 14: 1802–1815.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rakowski, E. 1991. Equal justice. Oxford: Clarendon. Rakowski, E. 1991. Equal justice. Oxford: Clarendon.
Zurück zum Zitat Resier, S.J. 1985. Responsibility for personal health: A historical perspective. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10(1): 512–525. Resier, S.J. 1985. Responsibility for personal health: A historical perspective. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10(1): 512–525.
Zurück zum Zitat Resnik, D.B. 2007. Responsibility for health: Personal, social, and environmental. Journal of Medical Ethics 33: 444–445.PubMedCrossRef Resnik, D.B. 2007. Responsibility for health: Personal, social, and environmental. Journal of Medical Ethics 33: 444–445.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Roberts, C. 2006. What can I do to help myself?’ Somatic individuality and contemporary hormonal bodies. Science Studies 19: 2. Roberts, C. 2006. What can I do to help myself?’ Somatic individuality and contemporary hormonal bodies. Science Studies 19: 2.
Zurück zum Zitat Rodriguez-Osorio CA., and G. Dominguez-Cherit. 2008. Medical decision making: paternalism versus patient-centered (autonomous) care. Current Opinion in Critical Care 14(6): 708–13. Rodriguez-Osorio CA., and G. Dominguez-Cherit. 2008. Medical decision making: paternalism versus patient-centered (autonomous) care. Current Opinion in Critical Care 14(6): 708–13.
Zurück zum Zitat Rose, G. 1994. The strategy of preventive medicine. Oxford: Oxford U P. Rose, G. 1994. The strategy of preventive medicine. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Sandman, L., and C. Munthe. 2009. Shared decision-making and patient autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 30: 289–310.PubMedCrossRef Sandman, L., and C. Munthe. 2009. Shared decision-making and patient autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 30: 289–310.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe to each other?. Harvard: Harvard U P. Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe to each other?. Harvard: Harvard U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Schmidt, H. 2009b. Personal responsibility in the NHS constitution and the social determinants health approach: Competitive or complementary. Health Economics, Policy and Law 4: 129–138.CrossRef Schmidt, H. 2009b. Personal responsibility in the NHS constitution and the social determinants health approach: Competitive or complementary. Health Economics, Policy and Law 4: 129–138.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schmidt, H., A. Gerber, and S. Stock. 2009. What can we learn from German health incentive schemes? British Medical Journal 339: 725–728.CrossRef Schmidt, H., A. Gerber, and S. Stock. 2009. What can we learn from German health incentive schemes? British Medical Journal 339: 725–728.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Scruton, R. 2000. The risks of being risk-free. Wall Street Journal 52(12): 256–275. Scruton, R. 2000. The risks of being risk-free. Wall Street Journal 52(12): 256–275.
Zurück zum Zitat Segall, S. 2009. Health, luck and justice. Princeton: Princeton U P. Segall, S. 2009. Health, luck and justice. Princeton: Princeton U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Sharkey, K., and L. Gillam. 2010. Should patients with self-inflicted illness receive lower priority in access to healthcare resources? Mapping out the debate. Journal of Medical Ethics 36: 661–665.PubMedCrossRef Sharkey, K., and L. Gillam. 2010. Should patients with self-inflicted illness receive lower priority in access to healthcare resources? Mapping out the debate. Journal of Medical Ethics 36: 661–665.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sidgwick, H. 1907. The methods of ethics. London: Macmillan. Sidgwick, H. 1907. The methods of ethics. London: Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Stewart, D.C., G.B. Anthony, and R. Chesson. 2010. ‘It’s not my job. I’m the patient not the doctor’: Patient perspectives on medicines management in the treatment of schizophrenia. Patient Education and Counseling 78: 212–217.PubMedCrossRef Stewart, D.C., G.B. Anthony, and R. Chesson. 2010. ‘It’s not my job. I’m the patient not the doctor’: Patient perspectives on medicines management in the treatment of schizophrenia. Patient Education and Counseling 78: 212–217.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Strawson, P. 1974. Freedom and resentment. In Freedom and resentment and other essays, 1–25. Methuen & Co. Strawson, P. 1974. Freedom and resentment. In Freedom and resentment and other essays, 1–25. Methuen & Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Strawson, G. 1986. Freedom and belief. Oxford: Oxford U P. Strawson, G. 1986. Freedom and belief. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Tännsjö, T. 1998. Hedonistic utilitarianism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P. Tännsjö, T. 1998. Hedonistic utilitarianism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U P.
Zurück zum Zitat Techman, B.A., K.D. Gapinski, K.D. Brownell, and M. Rawlins. 2003. Demonstrations of implicit anti-fat bias: The impact of providing causal information and evoking empathy. Health Psychology 22(1): 68–78.CrossRef Techman, B.A., K.D. Gapinski, K.D. Brownell, and M. Rawlins. 2003. Demonstrations of implicit anti-fat bias: The impact of providing causal information and evoking empathy. Health Psychology 22(1): 68–78.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Temkin, L.S. 1993. Inequality. Oxford: Oxford U P. Temkin, L.S. 1993. Inequality. Oxford: Oxford U P.
Zurück zum Zitat van Inwagen, P. 1983. An essay on free will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. van Inwagen, P. 1983. An essay on free will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Walker, T. 2010. Who do we treat first when the resources are scarce? Journal of Applied Philosophy 27(2): 200–211.CrossRef Walker, T. 2010. Who do we treat first when the resources are scarce? Journal of Applied Philosophy 27(2): 200–211.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wikler, D. 2002. Personal and social responsibility for health. Ethics & International Affairs 16(2): 47–55.CrossRef Wikler, D. 2002. Personal and social responsibility for health. Ethics & International Affairs 16(2): 47–55.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wilkinson, R. 2005. The impact of inequality—How to make sick societies healthier?. New York: New Press. Wilkinson, R. 2005. The impact of inequality—How to make sick societies healthier?. New York: New Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Williams, A. 1992. Cost-effective analysis: Is it ethical? Journal of Medical Ethics 18: 152–167.CrossRef Williams, A. 1992. Cost-effective analysis: Is it ethical? Journal of Medical Ethics 18: 152–167.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Williams, G.C., Z.R. Freedman, and E.L. Deci. 1998. Supporting autonomy to motivate patients with diabetes for glucose control. Diabetes Care 21: 1644–1651.PubMedCrossRef Williams, G.C., Z.R. Freedman, and E.L. Deci. 1998. Supporting autonomy to motivate patients with diabetes for glucose control. Diabetes Care 21: 1644–1651.PubMedCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat World Health Organisation. 2002. The world health report: Reducing risks, promoting healthy life. Geneva: WHO. World Health Organisation. 2002. The world health report: Reducing risks, promoting healthy life. Geneva: WHO.
Metadaten
Titel
The right perspective on responsibility for ill health
verfasst von
Karl Persson
Publikationsdatum
01.08.2013
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy / Ausgabe 3/2013
Print ISSN: 1386-7423
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8633
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-012-9432-6

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3/2013

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3/2013 Zur Ausgabe