Skip to main content
Erschienen in: International Journal for Equity in Health 1/2015

Open Access 01.12.2015 | Research

Unexplained health inequality – is it unfair?

verfasst von: Yukiko Asada, Jeremiah Hurley, Ole Frithjof Norheim, Mira Johri

Erschienen in: International Journal for Equity in Health | Ausgabe 1/2015

Abstract

Introduction

Accurate measurement of health inequities is indispensable to track progress or to identify needs for health equity policy interventions. A key empirical task is to measure the extent to which observed inequality in health – a difference in health – is inequitable. Empirically operationalizing definitions of health inequity has generated an important question not considered in the conceptual literature on health inequity. Empirical analysis can explain only a portion of observed health inequality. This paper demonstrates that the treatment of unexplained inequality is not only a methodological but ethical question and that the answer to the ethical question – whether unexplained health inequality is unfair – determines the appropriate standardization method for health inequity analysis and can lead to potentially divergent estimates of health inequity.

Methods

We use the American sample of the 2002–03 Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health and measure health by the Health Utilities Index (HUI). We model variation in the observed HUI by demographic, socioeconomic, health behaviour, and health care variables using Ordinary Least Squares. We estimate unfair HUI by standardizing fairness, removing the fair component from the observed HUI. We consider health inequality due to factors amenable to policy intervention as unfair. We contrast estimates of inequity using two fairness-standardization methods: direct (considering unexplained inequality as ethically acceptable) and indirect (considering unexplained inequality as unfair). We use the Gini coefficient to quantify inequity.

Results

Our analysis shows that about 75% of the variation in the observed HUI is unexplained by the model. The direct standardization results in a smaller inequity estimate (about 60% of health inequality is inequitable) than the indirect standardization (almost all inequality is inequitable).

Conclusions

The choice of the fairness-standardization method is ethical and influences the empirical health inequity results considerably. More debate and analysis is necessary regarding which treatment of the unexplained inequality has the stronger foundation in equity considerations.
Hinweise

Electronic supplementary material

The online version of this article (doi:10.​1186/​s12939-015-0138-2) contains supplementary material, which is available to authorized users.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

YA conceived and designed the study and analyzed the data, and JH, OFN, and MJ critically contributed to the conception, design, and analysis. All authors critically contributed to interpret results. YA and JH drafted the manuscript. All authors contributed to critical revisions of the manuscript for important intellectual content. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.
Abkürzungen
BMI
Body mass index
CI
Confidence intervals
CLAD
Censored least absolute deviation
HUI
Health utilities index
JCUSH
Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health
OLS
Ordinary least squares
US
United States

Introduction

Inequalities and inequities in health care and health outcomes continue to be in the center stage of health policy in many jurisdictions. Accurate measurement of inequalities and inequities is indispensable to track progress or to identify needs for policy interventions [1,2]. Regular reporting of health inequalities and inequities requires ongoing data and methodological improvement. Measurement of health inequities is more challenging than that of health inequalities not only for their requirements for data on determinants of health [3] but also for ethical considerations. Health inequities are a subset of ethically problematic health inequalities – differences in health –, and their measurement demands a definition of health inequity and operationalization of the chosen definition in the measurement exercises [4,5].
To date, no single, agreed-up definition of health inequities exists. Alternative definitions of health inequity can be distinguished by the sources of health inequality each classified as ethically acceptable and unacceptable. For example, Braveman and Gruskin define health equity as “the absence of systematic disparities in health … between social groups who have different levels of underlying social advantage/disadvantage” ([6], p. 254). This view thus regards inequalities associated with social advantage as ethically unacceptable. In contrast, equal opportunity for health, a definition gaining popularity in the health economics literature [7-10], considers health inequality due to factors beyond individual control is unfair. In this view, factors within individual control are ethically acceptable sources of inequality.
Given that the ultimate focus of policy concern is health inequities, a key empirical task is to measure the extent to which observed inequality in health is inequitable. This requires an integration of the conceptual and empirical literatures on health inequity [4,5,11,12]. Empirically operationalizing definitions of health inequity has generated an important question not considered in the conceptual literature on health inequity noted above [7,11,12]. Empirical analysis can explain only a portion of observed health inequality. The presence of large unexplained variation in health regression models is no news to methodologists, who typically consider it as a data or methodological limitation. However, in the measurement of health inequity, a question arises as to how we should classify unexplained health inequality – fair or unfair. This ethical question is unavoidable in such empirical exercises, and different answers to this question can result in divergent health inequity results, some of which are fundamental to health equity policy, such as how much health inequity exists in the population, and to what degree observed health inequality is inequitable. Despite potentially large policy implications, the issue of unexplained health inequality has not received sufficient attention in health services and population health research and policy.
The goal of this paper is to demonstrate that the answer to the ethical question – whether unexplained health inequality is unfair – determines the choice of the standardization method and can lead to potentially divergent estimates of health inequity. In the next section, we explain how this question arises in the assessment of health inequities and articulate how answers to this question lead to particular methodological choices. We then demonstrate the importance of this ethical question empirically using the Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health (JCUSH) [13], which is typical of the data available for health inequity analysis. Our analysis shows that different ethical judgments regarding unexplained health inequality lead to substantial differences in estimates of health inequity. We conclude by discussing future research directions to enhance understanding of this issue.

Ethical judgments regarding unexplained health inequality in health inequity analysis

The issue of unexplained health inequality arises in an effort to be transparent and explicit about the definition of health inequity when empirically measuring health inequity. Measuring health inequity requires individual-level data to model variation in health at the individual level. Assuming that we have such individual-level health survey data, we begin by quantifying the amount of inequality in the distribution of observed health across individuals. We can use a univariate inequality index (e.g., Gini index). This provides a measure of the total amount of health inequality in the population.
To measure health inequity, we must quantify the distribution of unfair health across individuals in the population, that is, unfair health inequality. Unfair health, however, is not directly observable. To estimate it from observed health, we first model variation in health. The goal is to statistically explain as much variation in health as possible with the data at hand. This enables us to partition variation in health into that attributable to factors considered fair, or legitimate, sources of variation, and that attributable to factors considered unfair, or non-legitimate, source of variation. In other words, to define health inequities we need to look at causes of health inequalities [11].
As an example, let us consider a popular definition of health inequity, policy amenability, which argues that health inequality due to factors amenable to policy intervention is unfair [14]. We classify each variable in our data as a legitimate (ethically acceptable) source of inequality – that is, it is not amenable to policy intervention – or an illegitimate (ethically unacceptable) source of inequality – that is, it is amenable to policy intervention. Table 1 is an example of such legitimate-illegitimate classification based on the perspective of policy amenability. We assume age largely represents the biological association with health and treat it as the only variable that is not amenable to policy intervention, and thus, a legitimate source of variation in health. We classify all other variables as amenable to policy because: (a) it is possible to change the distribution of the variable (e.g., education, income), or (b) even when it is not possible to change the distribution of the variable, it is in principle possible to change how society treats people with the characteristic (e.g., for race and sex, it is possible to eliminate racial or sex discrimination). Age and sex capture both biology and social policy, and the asymmetrical treatment stems from our assumption as to which effect each of these variables represents most.
Table 1
Legitimate-illegitimate classification of variables according to the perspective of policy amenability
Variable
Legitimate vs. illegitimate classification
Demographics status
 
 Age
Legitimate
 Sex
Illegitimate
 Marital status
Illegitimate
 Race
Illegitimate
 Country of birth
Illegitimate
Health behaviour
 
 Smoker type and history
Illegitimate
 BMI
Illegitimate
 Frequency of physical activity
Illegitimate
Socioeconomic status
 
 Household income
Illegitimate
 Education
Illegitimate
Health care factors
 
 Has regular medical doctor
Illegitimate
 Unmet need
Illegitimate
 High blood pressure management
Illegitimate
 Asthma medication management
Illegitimate
 Pharmaceutical insurance
Illegitimate
 Health insurance type
Illegitimate
BMI: body mass index.
Variables are those we include in our analysis using the Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health (JCUSH).
“Policy amenability” argues that health inequality due to factors amenable to policy intervention is unfair [14].
A legitimate source of health inequality means that the variable is not amenable to policy, thus, resulting health inequality is ethically acceptable.
An illegitimate source of health inequality means that the variable is amenable to policy, thus, resulting health inequality is ethically unacceptable.
Classifications like that in Table 1 generate intense debate for at least two reasons. First, defining health inequity in this way assumes causality between health and the other variables, which cannot always be established empirically due to data and methodological limitations. Second, people debate passionately whether a particular source is legitimate or illegitimate. Our particular choices presented in Table 1 are only for illustrative purposes. The key point here is that, to estimate unfair health, one needs to classify variables as legitimate or illegitimate according to a chosen definition of health inequity.
Having classified each variable, we then remove the influence of the fair component – legitimate variables according to a chosen definition of health inequity – on the observed health through fairness-standardization. This leaves us with only inequality due to unfair sources. Fairness-standardization is similar to age-standardization in epidemiological studies, which removes the influence of age when estimating mortality rates, but in this context, standardization removes the influence of all legitimate sources of inequality. Consequently, the standardization generates the inequitable distribution of health in the population. The amount of inequity is then quantified by applying the same inequality index as above to this distribution of unfair health. Despite the use of the same mathematical index, the measure here is an index of inequity, as opposed to simply inequality, as it quantifies the distribution of unfair health.
For fairness-standardization, two methods are available: direct and indirect. As we show below, the choice of the standardization method is closely connected to ethical judgments regarding unexplained inequality.
Both direct and indirect standardization methods are based on the notion that the observed health consists of legitimate, illegitimate, and unexplained components:
$$ Observed\ HUI= Legitimate+ Illegitimate+ Unexplained $$
Using the direct standardization method, we predict unfair health directly by allowing only the illegitimate variables alone to influence the predictions. To do so, we purge the influence of legitimate variables by setting the value of these variables constant (expressed with the bar in the equation) during the prediction and ignore the unexplained component:
$$ Unfa{\widehat{ir\ HUI}}_{direct}=\overline{Legitimate}+ Illegitimate $$
As is clear, this produces a distribution in which the only source of variation in predicted levels of health arises from variation across individuals in illegitimate factors.
Using the indirect standardization, we first predict fair health by allowing only the legitimate variables to influence the predictions. To do so, we purge the influence of illegitimate variables (by holding their values at a constant during prediction) and ignore the unexplained component:
$$ F\widehat{air\ H}UI= Legitimate+\overline{Illegitimate} $$
We then calculate unfair health by subtracting the estimate of fair health from the observed health and adding the mean health of the population:
$$ \begin{array}{l} Unfai{\widehat{r\ HUI}}_{indirect}\\ {}= Observed\ HUI-F\widehat{air\ H}UI+ Populatio{n}^{\hbox{'}}s\ mean\ HUI\\ {}=\left( Legitimate+ Illegitimate+ Unexplained\right)- Legitimate + Populatio{n}^{\hbox{'}}s\ mean\ HUI\\ {}= Illegitimate+ Unexplained+ Populatio{n}^{\hbox{'}}s\ mean\ HUI\end{array} $$
This addition of the mean health of the population is conventional [15] and ensures that the distributions of the observed health and the unfair health have the same mean value.
For both standardization methods, we can choose any values at which to hold the relevant variables constant (legitimate variables for direct standardization and illegitimate for indirect standardization). But the choice reflects an ethical and policy judgment regarding the reference attributes by which we assess health inequity. For example, for the definition of policy amenability discussed above, we can hold each relevant variable at the category to which policies might reasonably aim (e.g., education at “high school”), or we could set the level to the healthiest category in the population (e.g., education at “university or college certificate”). Whether we should assess health inequity against a modest or ambitious goal depends on which differences in health we consider as unfair and what reference we consider as an appropriate policy goal. Just as the legitimate-illegitimate classification of variables, the choice of reference values can generate debate. For the purpose of this paper, which compares the two standardization methods, we set reference values equal to the modest goals as an example.
Importantly for the focus of this paper, notice that the unfair health estimated by the direct standardization does not include the unexplained component while the unfair health estimated by the indirect standardization does. The larger the unexplained component is, the greater the discrepancy is between unfair health estimated by these two standardization methods.
Notice further that the choice of the standardization methods implies ethical judgments: using the direct standardization, we regard unexplained variation in inequality as ethically acceptable, and using the indirect standardization, we regard it as unfair. Although this issue has been raised in the health economics literature [7,11,12], there has been little appreciation for these ethical judgments in the public health and health policy literatures. Below we illustrate how much difference these standardization methods can make in estimates of health inequity using typically available survey data.

Methods

Data

We estimate health inequity using the 2002–03 Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health (JCUSH), a cross-sectional population health survey jointly conducted by Statistics Canada and the U.S. National Center for Health Statistics [13]. The JCUSH questionnaire included questions regarding health status, health care utilization, health behaviour, socioeconomic status, and health insurance status. The target population was non-institutionalized Canadian and U.S. household residents aged 18 and older. The JCUSH used a complex sampling design with stratification by geographic region and oversampling of respondents aged 65 and over.
For simplicity and the ease of exposition, in this paper we present the results for the American sample only. The analysis using the Canadian sample yielded the same key methodological findings (available from the authors upon request). The original American sample of the JCUSH is 5,183 (response rate: 50.2%). We exclude observations with missing values (typically less than 4% of observations), except income (19.8%), for which we create “income missing” category. We also exclude 48 observations with scores of the Health Utilities Index (HUI), our measure of health, less than or equal to zero. The final sample size for our analysis is 4,328.

Variables

Health

We measure health by the Health Utilities Index Mark 3 (HUI), a well validated and widely used generic health-related quality of life measure [16]. The HUI measures the respondent’s functional levels in eight dimensions (vision, hearing, speech, mobility, dexterity, emotion, cognition, and pain) and converts his or her functional levels into a health-related quality-of-life score based on preferences of the general public (as opposed to the respondent’s preferences) over health states. One advantage of the HUI is that it is possible to identify when a difference in scores is meaningful for policy purposes. A difference of 0.030 or greater is meaningful or important [17], indicating the difference large enough to justify a recommendation for an intervention to achieve such an increment in health [18]. The observed distribution of HUI scores in the full sample range from −0.360 to 1.000 on a scale in which 0.000 represents being dead and 1.000 represents perfect health, and negative scores indicates health states worse than dead. For our analysis, we use only observations with zero or positive HUI scores as the Gini index, by which we measure univariate inequality and inequity, allows only non-negative values for the variable being analyzed [19].

Attributes known to be associated with health

We use a number of attributes known to be associated with health and available from the JCUSH: demographic status, health behaviour, socioeconomic status, and health care system factors, including the availability of basic health care, quality of health care, and health care insurance. We tested for interactions among these variables and retained the interaction terms between smoking and income and between body mass index (BMI) and education, which remain statistically significant at the 5% level in the final model.

Quantifying health inequality and inequity

We use the Gini coefficient to quantify health inequality and inequity [4,20]. The Gini coefficient takes values between zero (perfectly equal distribution) and one (most unequal). The Gini coefficient is widely used in the income inequality literature and has also been applied to quantify the distribution of health [21]. The Gini coefficient assumes that the underlying variable is measured at the ratio scale level. The HUI is an interval-scale measure, so our application of the Gini to the HUI violates this assumption. In practice, however, many inequality analyses apply the Gini to health measures that do not strictly satisfy this assumption, and given that the choice of inequality measure is not central to the main focus of our analysis, we believe our use of the Gini is reasonable. Although the 0–1 index of the Gini coefficient itself does not give an intuitive interpretation, twice the value of the Gini coefficient indicates the proportion of the expected mean difference between two randomly selected persons in the population [22]. For example, a value of 0.100 for the Gini coefficient with the mean HUI, 0.800, indicates that the expected difference in the HUI from two randomly drawn persons in this population is twice 0.100 (i.e., 0.200) of the mean HUI, 0.800 (i.e., 0.160). When the Gini coefficient in the population indicates the expected difference in the HUI from two randomly drawn persons equal to or greater than 0.030, the minimum magnitude for a difference in HUI scores to be policy relevant, we consider this inequality or inequity as policy relevant.

Analysis

The analysis proceeds with the following three steps. First, we estimate the magnitude of inequality in the observed HUI across individuals using the Gini coefficient. Second, we model variation in the observed HUI. Third, based on the definition of policy amenability, as discussed above, and using the direct and indirect standardization methods, we estimate unfair HUI for each individual and quantify the magnitude of inequity using the Gini coefficient. In both standardization methods, we hold relevant variable at the category to which policies might reasonably aim (see Additional file 1).
Modeling the distribution of the HUI is challenging because the HUI is bounded (between 0.000 and 1.000), it spikes at 1.0 (in our JCUSH sample, about 25% of the observations have HUI=1), and it is left-skewed. Researchers have recommended a number of alternative statistical methods to empirically model the distribution of HUI, including Ordinary Least Squares (OLS), Tobit, censored least absolute deviation (CLAD), two-part models, and latent class models, with no consensus regarding the best approach [23-26]. In this paper we present results from the OLS because OLS performed well relative to two-part models and CLAD in our sensitivity analysis and is easier to understand than the alternativesa.
We weight all analyses using the sample weights provided by the JCUSH. To estimate variance accounting for the JCUSH’s complex survey design, we use the balanced repeated replication methods with balanced repeated replication weights provided by Statistics Canada and the US National Center for Health Statistics. We consider p<0.05 as statistically significant. We use Stata 11 for all analyses [27,28].

Results

Sample characteristics

Sample characteristics and the average HUI across subgroups mostly follow expected patterns (Table 2). The average HUI is lower among older age groups; those separated, divorced, or widowed; black or other racial group; those with unmet need; those without pharmaceutical insurance; and those with Medicaid only. The average HUI does not differ much by sex or country of birth. Those with healthy behaviours and high socioeconomic status, measured by income or education, have higher average HUI. Those with no regular medical doctor and no health insurance have higher average HUI than those with regular medical doctor and health insurance, which may indicate younger age and less demand for health care among this group. High demand for health care may be a factor for lower average HUI among those with high blood pressure or asthma and received treatment or medication in the last 12 months than those with such conditions but who did not obtain treatment or medication.
Table 2
Sample characteristics
 
N (%)
HUI
Total sample
4, 328(100)
0.869
Demographics status
  
Age (year)
  
 18-44
1,962(45.33)
0.910
 45-64
1,470(33.96)
0.856
 65+
896(20.70)
0.800
Sex
  
 Men
1,899(43.88)
0.881
 Women
2,429(56.12)
0.860
Marital status
  
 Married or common law partner
2,443(56.45)
0.888
 Separated, divorced, or widowed
1,094(25.28)
0.812
 Single
791(18.28)
0.889
Race
  
 White
3,384(78.19)
0.874
 Other
500(11.55)
0.842
 Black
332(7.67)
0.843
 Asian
112(2.59)
0.918
Country of birth
  
 Foreign born
614(14.19)
0.867
 Native born
3,714(85.81)
0.869
Health behaviour
  
Smoker type and history
  
 Never smoked
2,259(52.20)
0.889
 Former smoker and started smoking at or after 18 years
717(16.57)
0.858
 Former smoker and started smoking before 18 years
342(7.90)
0.817
BMI
  
 Underweight
96(2.22)
0.820
 Normal weight
1,864(43.07)
0.890
 Overweight
1,455(33.62)
0.880
 Obese
913(21.10)
0.813
Frequency of physical activity
  
 Regular
2,518(58.18)
0.907
 Occasional
736(17.01)
0.885
 Infrequent
1,074(24.82)
0.768
Socioeconomic status
  
Household income
  
  Lowest income quintile
665(15.37)
0.769
  Lower middle income quintile
696(16.08)
0.855
  Middle income quintile
620(14.33)
0.894
  Higher middle income quintile
726(16.77)
0.909
  Highest middle income quintile
763(17.63)
0.930
  Income missing
858(19.82)
0.852
Education
  
  Less than high school
431(9.96)
0.756
  High school graduate
1,569(36.25)
0.856
  Non-university/college certificate
635(14.67)
0.867
  University/college certificate
1,693(39.12)
0.911
Health care factors
  
Has regular medical doctor
  
  No
786(18.16)
0.890
  Yes
3,542(81.84)
0.864
Unmet need
  
  No
3,816(88.84)
0.885
  Yes
512(11.83)
0.753
With high blood pressure and received treatment in the last 12 months
  
  No
54(1.25)
0.820
  Yes
832(19.22)
0.788
  No high blood pressure
3,442(79.53)
0.889
With asthma and received medication in the last 12 months
  
  No
190(4.39)
0.882
  Yes
280(6.47)
0.784
  No asthma
3,858(89.14)
0.875
Has pharmaceutical insurance
  
  No
881(20.36)
0.846
  Yes
3,447(79.64)
0.875
Health insurance type (US only)
  
  No insurance
443(10.24)
0.851
  Medicaid only
160(3.70)
0.677
  Non-Medecaid public only including Medicare
254(5.87)
0.758
  Private plus public including Medicare
818(18.90)
0.811
  Private only
2,653(61.30)
0.912
Data source: Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health (JCUSH).
BMI: body mass index; HUI: Health Utilities Index.
BMI is based on the World Health Organization. Underweight: <18.5 kg/m2; normal weight: 18.5-24.9 kg/m2; overweight: 25-30 kg/m2; obese >30 kg/m2.
HUI estimates are weighted and unadjusted.

Modeling variation in health (HUI)

The fit of our model is comparable to other work describing the variation in the HUI (adjusted R2: 0.258, Table 3) [29,30]. Among the demographic variables, only age is statistically significant. Lack of statistical significance of race is somewhat counter-intuitive but confirms other studies using the JCUSH (e.g., [30]). When we add socioeconomic variables to demographic variables, race becomes statistically insignificant, and, after introducing health care supply variables, the sign of the coefficient for black flips from negative to positive. All health behaviour variables (smoker type, BMI, and physical activity) and socioeconomic variables (income and education) show statistically significant effects on the HUI, either individually or through interactions. All health care supply variables are statistically significant, with the unmet need variable showing the largest coefficient (−0.110), followed by health insurance type (−0.092 for Medicaid only with no insurance as the reference).
Table 3
Results of ordinary least squares regression model for the health utilities index
 
Coefficient (95% CI)
p-value
Age (years, reference: 18-44)
 
0.000
 45-64
-0.044(-0.057, -0.030)
0.000
 65+
-0.013(-0.041, 0.015)
0.362
Male
-0.001(-0.012, 0.010)
0.890
Marital status (reference: single)
 
0.064
 Married or common law partner
-0.005(-0.010, 0.019)
0.554
 Separated, divorced, or widowed
-0.014(-0.034, 0.005)
0.155
Race (reference: White)
 
0.342
 Other
-0.006(-0.028, 0.016)
0.601
 Black
-0.016(-0.005, 0.037)
0.127
 Asian
-0.011(-0.046, 0.024)
0.546
Foreign born
-0.006(-0.013, 0.026)
0.515
Smoking (reference: never smoked)
 
0.059
 Former smoker and started smoking at or after 18 years
-0.052(-0.107, 0.002)
0.060
 Former smoker and started smoking before 18 years
-0.086(-0.170, 0.003)
0.043
 Current smoker and started smoking at or after 18 years
-0.015(-0.066, 0.036)
0.558
 Current smoker and started smoking before 18 years
-0.070(-0.140, 0.000)
0.050
BMI (reference: normal weight)
 
0.053
 Underweight
-0.166(-0.283, 0.048)
0.006
 Overweight
-0.025(-0.084, 0.034)
0.402
 Obese
-0.086(-0.084, 0.040)
0.485
Frequency of physical activity (reference; regular)
 
0.000
 Occasional
-0.012(-0.024, 0.001)
0.069
 Infrequent
-0.083(-0.099, -0.066)
0.000
Household income (reference: lowest income quintile)
 
0.122
 Lower middle income quintile
-0.021(-0.009, 0.050)
0.169
 Middle income quintile
-0.038(-0.010, 0.067)
0.009
 Higher middle income quintile
-0.036(-0.008, 0.064)
0.011
 Highest middle income quintile
-0.037(-0.008, 0.065)
0.011
 Income missing
-0.027(-0.001, 0.056)
0.056
Education (reference: less than high school)
 
0.026
 High school graduate
-0.007(-0.035, 0.049)
0.737
 Non-university/college certificate
-0.032(-0.013, 0.078)
0.162
 University/college certificate
-0.029(-0.013, 0.070)
0.176
Has regular medical doctor
-0.021(-0.036,-0.006)
0.005
Presence of self-reported unmet need
-0.110(-0.133,-0.087)
0.000
Treatment for high blood pressure in the last 12 months (reference: no treatment)
 
0.000
 Received treatment
-0.023(-0.081, 0.034)
0.424
 No high blood pressure
-0.020(-0.034, 0.073)
0.475
Medication for asthma in the last 12 months (reference: no medication)
 
0.008
 Received medication
-0.020(-0.076,-0.004)
0.031
 No asthma
-0.000(-0.026, 0.026)
0.999
Has pharmaceutical insurance
-0.032(-0.051, 0.013)
0.001
Health insurance type (US only, reference: no insurance)
 
0.000
 Medicaid only
-0.092(-0.146,-0.039)
0.001
 Non-Medicaid public only including Medicare
-0.052(-0.092,-0.013)
0.010
 Private plus public including Medicare
-0.038(-0.074, 0.001)
0.043
 Private only
-0.035(-0.008, 0.062)
0.010
Smoking x household income (reference: never smoked x lowest income quintile)
 
0.024
 Former smoker and started smoking at or after 18 years
  
  x Lower middle income quintile
0.011(-0.063, 0.085)
0.770
  x Middle income quintile
0.038(-0.024, 0.101)
0.225
  x Higher middle income quintile
0.050(-0.010, 0.111)
0.101
  x Highest middle income quintile
0.062(0.000, 0.124)
0.050
  x Income missing
0.086(-0.003, 0.122)
0.064
 Former smoker and started smoking before 18 years
  
  x Lower middle income quintile
0.041(-0.059, 0.141)
0.418
  x Middle income quintile
0.062(-0.035, 0.160)
0.210
  x Higher middle income quintile
0.105(0.015, 0.194)
0.023
  x Highest middle income quintile
0.094(0.004, 0.184)
0.041
  x Income missing
-0.003(-0.110, 0.105)
0.962
 Current smoker and started smoking at or after 18 years
  
  x Lower middle income quintile
0.027(-0.035, 0.088)
0.396
  x Middle income quintile
-0.022(-0.085, 0.040)
0.487
  x Higher middle income quintile
-0.010(-0.072, 0.053)
0.757
  x Highest middle income quintile
0.025(-0.033, 0.084)
0.393
  x Income missing
0.002(-0.061, 0.065)
0.955
 Current smoker and started smoking before 18 years
  
  x Lower middle income quintile
0.063(-0.016, 0.142)
0.116
  x Middle income quintile
0.002(-0.100, 0.103)
0.976
  x Higher middle income quintile
0.027(-0.058, 0.112)
0.531
  x Highest middle income quintile
0.094(-0.007, 0.180)
0.034
  x Income missing
0.002(-0.041, 0.141)
0.282
BMI x education (reference: normal weight x less than high school)
 
0.005
 Underweight
  
   x High school graduate
0.108(-0.038, 0.255)
0.147
  x Non-university/college certificate
0.159(-0.021, 0.340)
0.083
  x University/college certificate
0.176(-0.052, 0.301)
0.006
 Overweight
  
  x High school graduate
0.051(-0.012, 0.113)
0.112
  x Non-university/college certificate
0.014(-0.051, 0.080)
0.665
  x University/college certificate
0.022(-0.040, 0.083)
0.490
 Obese
  
  x High school graduate
-0.001(-0.068, 0.067)
0.985
  x Non-university/college certificate
-0.051(-0.128, 0.025)
0.190
  x University/college certificate
0.013(-0.051, 0.078)
0.683
Constant
0.919(0.839, 1.000)
0.000
Sample size
4328
 
Adjusted R-squared
0.258
 
Data source: Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health (JCUSH).
CI: confidence interval; BMI: body mass index.
P-value for each variable category is from t-test; p-value for the reference category is from F-test for all categories of each variable.
Analysis is weighted. Standard errors are adjusted for the complex survey design.

Health inequality

The far left data point of Figure 1 shows the magnitude of health inequality. The Gini coefficient for the distribution of the observed HUI is 0.094 (95% CI: 0.089, 0.100), and the mean HUI value for this distribution is 0.880 (95% confidence interval [CI]: 0.873, 0.886). Based on this information, the expected mean difference in the HUI of two randomly selected individuals is 0.165, which notably larger than the minimally policy significant difference in the HUI of 0.030.

Health inequity – the direct vs. indirect fairness-standardization method

As shown in Figure 1, the choice of the standardization method makes a substantial difference in estimates of health inequity. Using the direct standardization, the magnitude of health inequity, expressed by the Gini coefficient, is 0.059 (95% confidence interval [CI]: 0.058, 0.061), while using the indirect standardization, the Gini coefficient is 0.086 (95% CI: 0.082, 0.091). The large difference between these inequity estimates reflects the large amount of unexplained variation in health – the adjusted R2 for the regression model is 0.258, which indicates that about 75% of the variation in the observed HUI is not explained by the model. The direct standardization method presumes this large unexplained variation is fair, while the indirect method regards this unexplained variation as unfair.
Both inequity estimates are policy relevant. The Gini coefficients of 0.059 (the direct standardization) and of 0.086 (the indirect standardization) translate into the expected mean differences in the HUI of 0.101 and 0.166, respectively, between two randomly selected persons. These HUI values are more than three times larger than the minimally policy relevant difference of the HUI, 0.030.

Health inequality vs. health inequity

Figure 1 also shows that the choice of the standardization method influences the comparison between health inequality and health inequity. The Gini coefficient for the distribution of the observed HUI (0.094; 95% CI: 0.089, 0.100) is 1.6 times larger than the Gini coefficient for health inequity estimated by the direct standardization (0.059; 95% CI: 0.058, 0.061). However, the Gini coefficients for inequality and for inequity estimated by the indirect standardization (0.086; 95% CI: 0.082, 0.091) are not statistically significantly different. Therefore, the choice of the standardization method offers two contrasting results: About 60% of health inequality (the direct standardization) or almost all health inequality (the indirect standardization) we observe is inequitable.

Discussion

In the context of the empirical assessments of health inequities, this paper investigated the empirical importance of the ethical question of whether unexplained health inequality is unfair. The classification of unexplained inequality as fair or unfair is closely connected to the choice of the fairness-standardization methods, a critical step for the measurement of health inequities. As the analysis of the US component of the JCUSH showed, this choice can substantially influence the empirical results regarding how much health inequity exists in the population and the proportion of observed health inequality that is inequitable. We obtained the same results in analyses using the Canadian sample of the JCUSH and using a different definition of health inequity, equal opportunity for health (results not shown).
The question of how best to treat unexplained health inequality deserves more extensive consideration in the assessment of health inequities than it currently does. Both direct and indirect fairness-standardization methods are technically valid but can produce different health inequity information and imply different ethical stances in regard to unexplained variation. An analogy here may be the choice between direct and indirect age-standardization methods in epidemiological studies [31]. Both of these methods are sound but are known to produce different results. Analysts are therefore advised to be explicit and consistent about their methodological choice. What complicates the choice of the fairness-standardization methods is that it is not merely methodological but ethical.
Although unexplained health inequality is not an issue for those who subscribe to the view that all health inequalities are inequitable (for whom all observed variation – explained or unexplained – is unfair), it is an unavoidable issue for empirical analysts who do distinguish between pure health inequality and health inequity. Currently available data and modeling techniques enable analysts to explain only a relatively small portion of observed variation in health at the individual level. Because the issue of unexplained inequality only arises in empirical work, it has rarely been paid attention to in the conceptual discussion regarding definitions of health inequity. Still, some work in the recent detailed philosophical analysis of health inequity by philosophers, economists, and ethicists provides a hint as to how to consider the ethical significance of unexplained inequality.
To examine the ethical significance of unexplained inequality, it is useful to recognize that unexplained variation – residuals in a regression context – consists of two types of variation: variation systematically related to unobserved factors and random variation. The issue of unmeasured systematic variation stems from methodological limitations. Improved data, such as longitudinal data with a rich array of variables capturing individuals’ life history, and improved modeling techniques can reduce unmeasured systematic variation. As soon as unmeasured systematic variation becomes observed systematic variation, the question goes back to a familiar, on-going debate regarding definitions of health inequity, that is, which sources of health inequality are ethically unacceptable.
To assess the ethical significance of random variation, the philosophical literature distinguishes “brute luck” – unfortunate events from which even sensible persons suffer, such as being hit by lightning during the commute with no warning, or suffering from a genetic disease by chance (often referred to as genetic lottery) – and “option luck” – unfortunate events associated with voluntary risks, such as being hit by lightning while playing golf with a plenty of warning or getting injured during voluntary bungee jumping [32-34]. The philosophical literature offers a wide range of views regarding the ethical significance of brute and option luck. Some scholars consider neither option nor brute luck as unfair because only variations in health associated with known socially distributed determinants of health are unfair [35,36]. Alternatively, most equality in opportunity theories, also known as luck egalitarianism, consider that inequality caused by brute luck is unfair while that by option luck is fair [37]. Yet another view sees both brute and option luck as unfair [38]. To date, this philosophical literature has not caught attention in health services and population health research and policy, but it is an important literature in the face of large unexplained health inequality in empirical work.
Advances in data, modeling techniques, and philosophical arguments are ongoing processes, and the measurement and monitoring of health inequities for effective policy making cannot wait for their perfection. Three proposals are available for the treatment of unexplained health inequality in the current imperfect world that still urges policy making. First, Bago d’Uva, Jones, and van Doorslaer [39] recommend in the context of need-standardization for health care utilization, which faces a directly analogous problem, that analysts always provide two estimates of inequity, the lower bound estimate provided by the direct standardization and the upper bound estimate by the indirect standardization. This is a pragmatic stop-gap solution but passes the difficult ethical question to users of health inequity information. Second, given complex causal relationships between health and its determinants and the fact that we do not understand them fully, we might argue that it would be safer to assume unexplained health inequality is of ethical significance, that is, unfair [40,41]. This judgment, and policy decisions that follow from it, will come with some opportunity cost. Resources that are devoted to address health inequity based on this judgment could be directed to competing health or other social issues. We should at least know the nature of such opportunity cost before committing to such judgment.
Finally, Garcia-Gomez and colleagues [7] empirically investigate what unexplained health inequality is. They tested the view articulated by Lefranc and colleagues in the analysis of unexplained income inequality [42]: classify unexplained inequality as luck; examine whether the distribution of luck is uncorrelated with ethically unacceptable sources of inequality; and if that is the case, consider luck an ethically acceptable source of inequality. In their analysis of inequality in mortality among the Dutch population, they adopted the view of equal opportunity for health as the definition of health inequity, which argues that health inequality due to factors beyond individual control is unfair. They considered variables such as sex, age, and education as ethically unacceptable sources of inequality while variables such as smoking, exercise, and weight as ethically acceptable sources of inequality. They found that unexplained inequality is distributed differently across groups of people categorized by sex, age, and education with or without controlling for the health behaviour. In sum, their analysis suggests that unexplained inequality is not an ethically acceptable source of inequality.
Most of this emerging empirical work and its authors’ insight in into the importance of ethical discussion are of considerable significance for public health and health policy. Given potentially serious policy implications of the issue of unexplained health inequality, analysts should at least make their methodological choices explicit and report both results from both standardization methods whenever they can. Moving beyond this pragmatic solution, however, analysts need to spur more debate and analysis regarding which treatment of the unexplained inequality has the stronger foundation in equity considerations.

Endnote

aThe choice of the standardization methods would become even more ethically relevant if we used a non-linear model for the HUI. This means that, in a sense, our results using a linear model provide conservative estimates of the importance of this choice. We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

Acknowledgements

This study was supported by Nova Scotia Health Research Foundation (8677) and Canadian Institutes of Health Research (MPE 124739). Yukiko Asada was supported by a Canadian Institutes of Health Research New Investigator Award (MSH 87687). The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript. We gratefully acknowledge valuable comments from Dan Hausman, Larry Temkin, and participants of the polinomics seminar at the Centre for Health Economics and Policy Analysis at McMaster University and the Quebec Inter-University Center for Social Statistics conference: the social policy and health inequalities: An International perspective.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by/​4.​0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly credited. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://​creativecommons.​org/​publicdomain/​zero/​1.​0/​) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

YA conceived and designed the study and analyzed the data, and JH, OFN, and MJ critically contributed to the conception, design, and analysis. All authors critically contributed to interpret results. YA and JH drafted the manuscript. All authors contributed to critical revisions of the manuscript for important intellectual content. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.
Literatur
1.
Zurück zum Zitat Truman BI, Smith KC, Roy K, Chen Z, Moonesinghe R, Zhu J, et al. Rationale for regular reporting on health disparities and inequalities - United States. MMWR Surveill Summ. 2011;60 Suppl 01:3–10.PubMed Truman BI, Smith KC, Roy K, Chen Z, Moonesinghe R, Zhu J, et al. Rationale for regular reporting on health disparities and inequalities - United States. MMWR Surveill Summ. 2011;60 Suppl 01:3–10.PubMed
4.
Zurück zum Zitat Asada Y. Health inequality: Morality and measurement. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; 2007. Asada Y. Health inequality: Morality and measurement. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; 2007.
5.
Zurück zum Zitat Braveman P. Health disparities and health equity: concepts and measurement. Annu Rev Public Health. 2006;27:167–94.PubMedCrossRef Braveman P. Health disparities and health equity: concepts and measurement. Annu Rev Public Health. 2006;27:167–94.PubMedCrossRef
8.
Zurück zum Zitat Jusot F, Tubeuf S, Trannoy A. Circumstances and efforts: how important is their correlation for the measurement of inequality of opportunity in health? Health Econ. 2013;22:1470–95.PubMedCrossRef Jusot F, Tubeuf S, Trannoy A. Circumstances and efforts: how important is their correlation for the measurement of inequality of opportunity in health? Health Econ. 2013;22:1470–95.PubMedCrossRef
9.
Zurück zum Zitat Rosa Dias P. Inequality of opportunity in health: evidence from a UK cohort study. Health Econ. 2009;18:1057–74.PubMedCrossRef Rosa Dias P. Inequality of opportunity in health: evidence from a UK cohort study. Health Econ. 2009;18:1057–74.PubMedCrossRef
10.
Zurück zum Zitat Trannoy A, Tubeuf S, Jusot F, Devaux M. Inequality of opportunities in health in France: a first pass. Health Econ. 2009;19:921–38.CrossRef Trannoy A, Tubeuf S, Jusot F, Devaux M. Inequality of opportunities in health in France: a first pass. Health Econ. 2009;19:921–38.CrossRef
11.
Zurück zum Zitat Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E. Unfair inequalities in health and health care. J Health Econ. 2009;28:73–90.PubMedCrossRef Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E. Unfair inequalities in health and health care. J Health Econ. 2009;28:73–90.PubMedCrossRef
12.
Zurück zum Zitat Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E. Equity in health and health care. In: Pauly MV, Mcguire GG, Barros PP, editors. Handbook of Health Economics, vol. 2. Oxford: Elseview BV; 2012. p. 1003–92. Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E. Equity in health and health care. In: Pauly MV, Mcguire GG, Barros PP, editors. Handbook of Health Economics, vol. 2. Oxford: Elseview BV; 2012. p. 1003–92.
13.
Zurück zum Zitat Statistics Canada,United States National Center for Health Statistics. Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health: public use microdata file user guide. Ottawa: Statistics Canada; 2004. Statistics Canada,United States National Center for Health Statistics. Joint Canada/United States Survey of Health: public use microdata file user guide. Ottawa: Statistics Canada; 2004.
15.
Zurück zum Zitat O'Donnell O, van Doorslaer E, Wagstaff A, Lindelow M. Analyzing health equity using household survey data: A guide to techniques and their implementation. New York: The World Bank; 2007.CrossRef O'Donnell O, van Doorslaer E, Wagstaff A, Lindelow M. Analyzing health equity using household survey data: A guide to techniques and their implementation. New York: The World Bank; 2007.CrossRef
17.
Zurück zum Zitat Drummond M. Introducing economic and quality of life measurements into clinical studies. Ann Med. 2001;33:344–9.PubMedCrossRef Drummond M. Introducing economic and quality of life measurements into clinical studies. Ann Med. 2001;33:344–9.PubMedCrossRef
18.
Zurück zum Zitat Samsa G, Edelman D, Rothman ML, Williams GR, Lipscomb J, Matchar D. Determining clinically important differences in health status measures. Pharmacoeconomics. 1999;15:141–55.PubMedCrossRef Samsa G, Edelman D, Rothman ML, Williams GR, Lipscomb J, Matchar D. Determining clinically important differences in health status measures. Pharmacoeconomics. 1999;15:141–55.PubMedCrossRef
19.
Zurück zum Zitat Chen C-N, Tsaur T-W, Rhai T-S. The Gini coefficient and negative income. Oxf Econ Pap. 1982;34:473–8. Chen C-N, Tsaur T-W, Rhai T-S. The Gini coefficient and negative income. Oxf Econ Pap. 1982;34:473–8.
21.
Zurück zum Zitat Smits J, Monden C. Length of life inequality around the globe. Soc Sci Med. 2009;68:1114–23.PubMedCrossRef Smits J, Monden C. Length of life inequality around the globe. Soc Sci Med. 2009;68:1114–23.PubMedCrossRef
22.
Zurück zum Zitat Atkinson AB. Health inequality, health inequity and health spending. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 27–36.CrossRef Atkinson AB. Health inequality, health inequity and health spending. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 27–36.CrossRef
23.
Zurück zum Zitat Huang IC, Frangakis C, Atkinson MJ, Willke RJ, Leite WL, Vogel WB, et al. Addressing ceiling effects in health status measures: a comparison of techniques applied to measures for people with HIV disease. Health Serv Res. 2008;43:327–39.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef Huang IC, Frangakis C, Atkinson MJ, Willke RJ, Leite WL, Vogel WB, et al. Addressing ceiling effects in health status measures: a comparison of techniques applied to measures for people with HIV disease. Health Serv Res. 2008;43:327–39.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef
24.
Zurück zum Zitat Li L, Fu AZ. Some methodological issues with the analysis of preference-based EQ-5D index score. Health Serv Outcomes Res Methodol. 2009;9:162–76.CrossRef Li L, Fu AZ. Some methodological issues with the analysis of preference-based EQ-5D index score. Health Serv Outcomes Res Methodol. 2009;9:162–76.CrossRef
25.
Zurück zum Zitat Pullenayegum EM, Tarride JE, Xie F, Goeree R, Gerstein HC, O'Reilly D. Analysis of health utility data when some subjects attain the upper bound of 1: are Tobit and CLAD models appropriate? Value Health. 2010;13:487–94.PubMedCrossRef Pullenayegum EM, Tarride JE, Xie F, Goeree R, Gerstein HC, O'Reilly D. Analysis of health utility data when some subjects attain the upper bound of 1: are Tobit and CLAD models appropriate? Value Health. 2010;13:487–94.PubMedCrossRef
26.
Zurück zum Zitat Sullivan PW, Ghushchyan V. Mapping the EQ-5D index from the SF-12: US general population preferences in a nationally representative sample. Med Decis Making. 2006;26:401–9.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef Sullivan PW, Ghushchyan V. Mapping the EQ-5D index from the SF-12: US general population preferences in a nationally representative sample. Med Decis Making. 2006;26:401–9.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef
28.
Zurück zum Zitat StataCorp. Stata statistical software: release 11.0. College Station, Texas: Stata Corporation; 2009. StataCorp. Stata statistical software: release 11.0. College Station, Texas: Stata Corporation; 2009.
30.
Zurück zum Zitat McGrail KM, van Doorslaer E, Ross NA, Sanmartin C. Income-related health inequalities in Canada and the United States: a decomposition analysis. Am J Public Health. 2009;99:1856–63.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef McGrail KM, van Doorslaer E, Ross NA, Sanmartin C. Income-related health inequalities in Canada and the United States: a decomposition analysis. Am J Public Health. 2009;99:1856–63.PubMedCentralPubMedCrossRef
31.
Zurück zum Zitat Gordis L. Epidemiology. Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders Company; 1996. Gordis L. Epidemiology. Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders Company; 1996.
32.
Zurück zum Zitat Cappelen AW, Norheim OF, Tungodden B. Genomics and equal opportunity ethics. J Med Ethics. 2008;34:361–4.PubMedCrossRef Cappelen AW, Norheim OF, Tungodden B. Genomics and equal opportunity ethics. J Med Ethics. 2008;34:361–4.PubMedCrossRef
33.
Zurück zum Zitat Dworkin R. What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy Public Affairs. 1981;10:185–246. Dworkin R. What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy Public Affairs. 1981;10:185–246.
34.
Zurück zum Zitat Dworkin R. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy Public Affairs. 1981;10:283–345. Dworkin R. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy Public Affairs. 1981;10:283–345.
35.
Zurück zum Zitat Hausman D. Egalitarian critiques of health inequalities. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 95–112.CrossRef Hausman D. Egalitarian critiques of health inequalities. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 95–112.CrossRef
36.
Zurück zum Zitat Marmot M. Fair society, healthy lives. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 282–98.CrossRef Marmot M. Fair society, healthy lives. In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 282–98.CrossRef
37.
Zurück zum Zitat Segall S. Health, luck, and justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2010. Segall S. Health, luck, and justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2010.
38.
Zurück zum Zitat Anderson ES. What is the point of equality? Ethics. 1999;109:287–337.CrossRef Anderson ES. What is the point of equality? Ethics. 1999;109:287–337.CrossRef
39.
Zurück zum Zitat Bago d'Uva T, Jones AM, van Doorslaer E. Measurement of horizontal inequity in health care utilisation using European panel data. J Health Econ. 2009;28:280–9.PubMedCrossRef Bago d'Uva T, Jones AM, van Doorslaer E. Measurement of horizontal inequity in health care utilisation using European panel data. J Health Econ. 2009;28:280–9.PubMedCrossRef
40.
Zurück zum Zitat Deaton A. What does the empirical evidence tell us about the injustice of health inequalities? In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 263–381.CrossRef Deaton A. What does the empirical evidence tell us about the injustice of health inequalities? In: Eyal N, Hurst S, Norheim OF, Wikler D, editors. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. p. 263–381.CrossRef
41.
Zurück zum Zitat Temkin L. Rethinking the good: moral ideals and the nature of practical reasoning. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. Temkin L. Rethinking the good: moral ideals and the nature of practical reasoning. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013.
42.
Zurück zum Zitat Lefranc A, Pistolesi N, Trannoy A. Equality of opportunity and luck: Definitions and testable conditions, with an application to income in France. J Public Econ. 2009;93:1189–207.CrossRef Lefranc A, Pistolesi N, Trannoy A. Equality of opportunity and luck: Definitions and testable conditions, with an application to income in France. J Public Econ. 2009;93:1189–207.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Unexplained health inequality – is it unfair?
verfasst von
Yukiko Asada
Jeremiah Hurley
Ole Frithjof Norheim
Mira Johri
Publikationsdatum
01.12.2015
Verlag
BioMed Central
Erschienen in
International Journal for Equity in Health / Ausgabe 1/2015
Elektronische ISSN: 1475-9276
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1186/s12939-015-0138-2

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2015

International Journal for Equity in Health 1/2015 Zur Ausgabe