Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Neuroethics 3/2011

01.11.2011 | Original Paper

Neural Lie Detection, Criterial Change, and OrdinaryLanguage

verfasst von: Thomas Nadelhoffer

Erschienen in: Neuroethics | Ausgabe 3/2011

Einloggen, um Zugang zu erhalten

Abstract

Michael Pardo and Dennis Patterson have recently put forward several provocative and stimulating criticisms that strike at the heart of much work that has been done at the crossroads of neuroscience and the law. My goal in this essay is to argue that their criticisms of the nascent but growing field of neurolaw are ultimately based on questionable assumptions concerning the nature of the ever evolving relationship between scientific discovery and ordinary language. For while the marriage between ordinary language and scientific discovery is admittedly not always a happy one, it is an awkward union that nevertheless seems to work itself out with the passage of time. In the following pages, I will try to show that Pardo and Patterson’s primary argumentative strategy ultimately depends on basic assumptions concerning the fixity of language that we should reject.
Fußnoten
1
See, also, Pardo and Patterson [2].
 
2
See, e.g., Hacker [3]; Bennett and Hacker [4]; Murphy and Brown [5]; Morse [6, 7]; Noe [8].
 
3
It is worth pointing out that the term “neurolaw” refers to a growing interdisciplinary field of inquiry that explores the relationship between neuroscience and the law. As such, neurolaw is neither an intellectual movement nor is it tied to a certain ideological point of view. Just as some researchers push a revolutionary agenda whereby neuroscience ought to be used to overthrow traditional legal categories (see, e.g., Greene and Cohen [9]), other researchers adopt a much more conservative approach to the relationship between law and neuroscience (see, e.g., Morse [6]). Given this very wide spectrum of views, it is a mistake to identify the overall field of neurolaw with particular positions within the field.
 
4
I think the argument could even be made that we have Wittgensteinian grounds for resisting the conventionalism of Pardo and Patterson, but that will not be one of my direct goals in this commentary.
 
5
The claim by Joshua Greene and Jonathan Cohen that “you are your brain” [9, p. 1779] is identified by Pardo and Patterson as one of their primary targets. We will unpack Greene and Cohen’s views concerning the relationship between the self and the brain in more detail in §3.
 
6
We may sometimes talk about a “happy tooth”—e.g., if we just had an aching tooth repaired—but here we are using “happy” in a very loose way. In a similar way, we may talk about Paige’s “smiling on the inside” as well—but here again, we would be using “smiling” very loosely. Moreover, the criteria we would rely on in trying to ascertain whether Paige really is “smiling on the inside” would themselves be behavioral criteria.
 
7
Bennett and Hacker call the principle that is purportedly being violated “the mereological principle.” As they say, “We have bluntly asserted the mereological principle in neuroscience, insisting that it is a logical principle, and therefore not amenable to empirical, experimental, confirmation or disconfirmation. It is indeed a convention, but one that determines what does and does not make sense. Its application—for example, to psychological concepts—could, in principle be changed by stipulation, but not without changing a great deal else, thereby altogether changing the meanings of our words and the structure of the multitude of familiar concepts. For the principle that psychological predicates apply to the animal as a whole and cannot be applied to its parts is held in place by a ramifying network of conceptual connections.” [4, p. 81]. This is an issue that has recently been discussed at length by Noe [8] as well.
 
8
See, e.g., Wittgenstein [1, 10].
 
9
Pardo and Patterson are careful to point out that they are not suggesting that knowledge “just is the relevant behavior”—since it is clearly possible both to (a) “have knowledge without expressing it,” and to (b) “engage in the relevant behavior without in fact having knowledge.” But if satisfying the behavioral criteria is neither necessary nor sufficient for knowledge, it is unclear why these criteria ought to be exclusively used to delineate what can meaningfully be said about knowledge.
 
10
Neuroscience-based lie detection is also sometimes called brain-based lie detection. In this paper, I am simply going to use “neural lie detection” for short.
 
11
There are actually at least five distinct methods that are presently being developed that use neuroscience in one form or another for the purposes of lie detection. See Greely [11, p.48] for a discussion of these methods as well as their respective shortcomings. To date, there have been a limited number of peer reviewed studies on neural lie detection. Pardo and Patterson mention Kozol et al. [12] and Langleben et al. [13]. See, also, Davatzikos et al. [14]; Ganis et al. [15]; Langleben et al. [16]; Lee et al. [17]; Mohamed et al. [18]; Nunez et al. [19]; Spence et al. [20].
 
12
The most recent study on neural lie detection—and arguably the most promising—is found in Greene and Paxton [21]. Their experimental design addresses several of the most prominent shortcomings of previous attempts to use fMRI for purposes of detecting honesty and deception.
 
13
See, e.g., Farah and Wolpe [22]; Garland and Glimcher [23]; Greely [11]; Greely and Illes [24]; Kanwisher [25]; Kittay [26]; Langleben [27]; Moreno [28]; Morse [7]; Phelps [29]; Rakoff [30]; Schauer [31]; Sinnott-Armstrong et al. [32]; Spence [33]. For discussions of neural lie detection in the popular press, see Henig [34]; Narayan [35]; Silberman [36].
 
14
I agree with Koethe [40] that “For all the use Wittgenstein makes of the notion of criteria, he offers very little in the way of an explanation of it” (p. 603).
 
15
See, e.g., Albritton [41]; Caraway [38, 42]; Chihara and Fodor [43]; Garver [44]; Hollinger [45]; Kenny [46]; Koethe [40]; Malcolm [47]; Putnam [48]; Scriven [49]. For a review of the early literature on the Wittgensteinian notion of criteria, see Lycan [50].
 
16
Philosophers and psychologists who work in the nascent field of experimental philosophy often probe precisely these kind of folk intuitions with an eye towards shedding light on first-order philosophical problems. For general introductions to experimental philosophy, see Knobe [51]; Knobe and Nichols [52]; and Nadelhoffer and Nahmias [53].
 
17
The general issue I am highlighting here was the motivating issue behind the influential debate between Norman Malcolm and Hilary Putnam concerning the relationship between criteria, ordinary language, and scientific discover. See, e.g., Hollinger [45]; Kenny [46]; Malcolm [47]; Putnam [48]. But since Pardo and Patterson did not frame their criticisms of neurolaw in terms of this salient earlier debate, I will set aside the details for now.
 
18
Obviously, language cannot be too fluid. There need to be some rules that stand firm so that others can change. The issue we are talking about here, however, is not about the limits of language’s fluidity. Instead, we are merely interested in whether the criteria of ordinary language are capable of change, expansion, or even fundamental revision.
 
19
The complete quote is as follows: “It is not as if there is a you, the composer, and then your brain, the orchestra. You are your brain, and your brain is the composer and the orchestra all rolled together. There is no little man, no ‘homunculus’, in the brain that is the real you behind the mass of neuronal instrumentation” [9, p. 1779].
 
20
The main issue I am interested in here is not merely exegetical. As such, my concern is not so much with what Greene and Cohen “really meant” but rather whether Pardo and Patterson have appropriately understood the real thrust of the reductive views they reject.
 
21
It is worth pointing out that it is true that ordinary language historically relied heavily—if not exclusively—on behavioral criteria. As such, it is unsurprising that so many concepts have the sorts of criteria highlighted by Pardo and Patterson. However, the issue is not the ubiquity of behavioral criteria when it comes to ordinary language. Rather, the issue is whether we ought to use the present behavioral criteria as the sole and definitive normative guideline for distinguishing sense from non-sense.
 
Literatur
1.
Zurück zum Zitat Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe and Georg H. von Wright. Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe and Georg H. von Wright.
2.
Zurück zum Zitat Pardo, M., and D. Patterson. 2010. Philosophical foundations of law and neuroscience. Illinois Law Review, forthcoming. Pardo, M., and D. Patterson. 2010. Philosophical foundations of law and neuroscience. Illinois Law Review, forthcoming.
3.
Zurück zum Zitat Hacker, P.M.S. 2007. The relevance of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology to the psychological sciences. Proceedings of the Leipzig Conference on Wittgenstein and Science. Hacker, P.M.S. 2007. The relevance of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology to the psychological sciences. Proceedings of the Leipzig Conference on Wittgenstein and Science.
4.
Zurück zum Zitat Bennett, M.R., and P.M.S. Hacker. 2003. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell. Bennett, M.R., and P.M.S. Hacker. 2003. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.
5.
Zurück zum Zitat Murphy, N., and W.S. Brown. 2007. Did my neurons make me do it? New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Murphy, N., and W.S. Brown. 2007. Did my neurons make me do it? New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
6.
Zurück zum Zitat Morse, S. 2007. The non-problem of free will in forensic psychiatry and psychology. Behavioral Sciences & the Law 25: 203–220.CrossRef Morse, S. 2007. The non-problem of free will in forensic psychiatry and psychology. Behavioral Sciences & the Law 25: 203–220.CrossRef
7.
Zurück zum Zitat Morse, S. 2009. Actions speak louder than images. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 23–34. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Morse, S. 2009. Actions speak louder than images. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 23–34. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
8.
Zurück zum Zitat Noe, A. 2009. Out of our heads. New York: Hill and Wang. Noe, A. 2009. Out of our heads. New York: Hill and Wang.
9.
Zurück zum Zitat Greene, J.D. and J.D. Cohen 2004. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B (Special Issue on Law and the Brain) 359: 1775–1785. Greene, J.D. and J.D. Cohen 2004. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B (Special Issue on Law and the Brain) 359: 1775–1785.
10.
Zurück zum Zitat Wittgenstein, L. 1953/2001. Philosophical investigations: 50th anniversary edition. Oxford: Blackwell. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Wittgenstein, L. 1953/2001. Philosophical investigations: 50th anniversary edition. Oxford: Blackwell. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe.
11.
Zurück zum Zitat Greely, H. 2009. Neuroscience-based lie detection: The need for regulation. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. E. Bizzi et al. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Greely, H. 2009. Neuroscience-based lie detection: The need for regulation. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. E. Bizzi et al. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
12.
Zurück zum Zitat Kozel, F., K. Johnson, Q. Mu, E. Grenesko, S. Laken, and M. George. 2005. Detecting deception using functional magnetic resonance imaging. Biological Psychiatry 58: 605.CrossRef Kozel, F., K. Johnson, Q. Mu, E. Grenesko, S. Laken, and M. George. 2005. Detecting deception using functional magnetic resonance imaging. Biological Psychiatry 58: 605.CrossRef
13.
Zurück zum Zitat Langleben, D., L. Schroeder, J. Maldjian, R.C. Gur, S. McDonald, J.D. Ragland, et al. 2002. Brain activity during simulated deception: An event-related functional magnetic resonance study. Neuroimage 15: 727.CrossRef Langleben, D., L. Schroeder, J. Maldjian, R.C. Gur, S. McDonald, J.D. Ragland, et al. 2002. Brain activity during simulated deception: An event-related functional magnetic resonance study. Neuroimage 15: 727.CrossRef
14.
Zurück zum Zitat Davatzikos, C., K. Ruparel, Y. Fan, D.G. Shen, M. Acharyya, J.W. Loughead, R.C. Gur, and D.D. Langleben. 2005. Classifying spatial patterns of brain activity with machine learning methods: Application to lie detection. Neuroimage 28: 663.CrossRef Davatzikos, C., K. Ruparel, Y. Fan, D.G. Shen, M. Acharyya, J.W. Loughead, R.C. Gur, and D.D. Langleben. 2005. Classifying spatial patterns of brain activity with machine learning methods: Application to lie detection. Neuroimage 28: 663.CrossRef
15.
Zurück zum Zitat Ganis, G., S.M. Kosslyn, S. Stose, W.L. Thompson, and D.A. Yurgelun-Todd. 2003. Neural correlates of different types of deception: An fMRI investigation. Cerebral Cortex 13: 830.CrossRef Ganis, G., S.M. Kosslyn, S. Stose, W.L. Thompson, and D.A. Yurgelun-Todd. 2003. Neural correlates of different types of deception: An fMRI investigation. Cerebral Cortex 13: 830.CrossRef
16.
Zurück zum Zitat Langleben, D., J. Loughead, W. Bilker, K. Ruparel, A.R. Childress, S. Busch, and R.C. Gur. 2005. Telling truth from lie in individual subjects with fast event-related fMRI. Human Brain Mapping 26: 262.CrossRef Langleben, D., J. Loughead, W. Bilker, K. Ruparel, A.R. Childress, S. Busch, and R.C. Gur. 2005. Telling truth from lie in individual subjects with fast event-related fMRI. Human Brain Mapping 26: 262.CrossRef
17.
Zurück zum Zitat Lee, T.M.C., H. Liu, L. Tan, C. Chan, S. Mahankali, C. Feng, J. Hou, P. Fox, and J. Gao. 2002. Lie detection by functional magnetic resonance imaging. Human Brain Mapping 15: 157.CrossRef Lee, T.M.C., H. Liu, L. Tan, C. Chan, S. Mahankali, C. Feng, J. Hou, P. Fox, and J. Gao. 2002. Lie detection by functional magnetic resonance imaging. Human Brain Mapping 15: 157.CrossRef
18.
Zurück zum Zitat Mohamed, F.B., et al. 2006. Brain mapping of deception and truth telling about an ecologically valid situation: Function MR imaging and polygraph investigation—initial experience. Radiology 238: 679.CrossRef Mohamed, F.B., et al. 2006. Brain mapping of deception and truth telling about an ecologically valid situation: Function MR imaging and polygraph investigation—initial experience. Radiology 238: 679.CrossRef
19.
Zurück zum Zitat Nunez, J.M., B.J. Casey, T. Egner, T. Hare, and J. Hirsch. 2005. Intentional false responding shares neural substrates with response conflict and cognitive control. Neuroimage 25: 267.CrossRef Nunez, J.M., B.J. Casey, T. Egner, T. Hare, and J. Hirsch. 2005. Intentional false responding shares neural substrates with response conflict and cognitive control. Neuroimage 25: 267.CrossRef
20.
Zurück zum Zitat Spence, S.A., T. Farrow, A. Herford, I. Wilkinson, Y. Zheng, and W.R. Peter. 2001. Behavioral and functional anatomical correlates of deception in humans. Brain Imaging Neuroreport 2849. Spence, S.A., T. Farrow, A. Herford, I. Wilkinson, Y. Zheng, and W.R. Peter. 2001. Behavioral and functional anatomical correlates of deception in humans. Brain Imaging Neuroreport 2849.
21.
Zurück zum Zitat Greene, J.D., and J.M. Paxton. 2009. Patterns of neural activity associated with honest and dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106(30): 12506–12511.CrossRef Greene, J.D., and J.M. Paxton. 2009. Patterns of neural activity associated with honest and dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106(30): 12506–12511.CrossRef
22.
Zurück zum Zitat Farah, M.J., and P.R. Wolpe. 2004. Monitoring and manipulating brain function: New neuroscience technologies and their ethical implications. The Hastings Center Report, Vol. 34. Farah, M.J., and P.R. Wolpe. 2004. Monitoring and manipulating brain function: New neuroscience technologies and their ethical implications. The Hastings Center Report, Vol. 34.
23.
Zurück zum Zitat Garland, B., and P. Glimcher. 2006. Cognitive neuroscience and the law. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 16(2): 130–134.CrossRef Garland, B., and P. Glimcher. 2006. Cognitive neuroscience and the law. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 16(2): 130–134.CrossRef
24.
Zurück zum Zitat Greely, H. T., and J. Illes. 2007. Neuroscience-based lie detection: The urgent need for regulation. American Journal of Law and Medicine 33(2–3): 377–431. Greely, H. T., and J. Illes. 2007. Neuroscience-based lie detection: The urgent need for regulation. American Journal of Law and Medicine 33(2–3): 377–431.
25.
Zurück zum Zitat Kanwisher, N. 2009. The use of fMRI in lie detection: What has been shown and what has not. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 7–13. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Kanwisher, N. 2009. The use of fMRI in lie detection: What has been shown and what has not. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 7–13. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
26.
Zurück zum Zitat Kittay, L. 2007. Admissibility of fMRI lie detection—the cultural bias against mind reading devices. Brooklyn Law Review 72: 1351. Kittay, L. 2007. Admissibility of fMRI lie detection—the cultural bias against mind reading devices. Brooklyn Law Review 72: 1351.
27.
Zurück zum Zitat Langleben, D. 2008. Detection of deception with fMRI: Are we there yet? Legal and Criminological Psychology 13(1): 1–9.CrossRef Langleben, D. 2008. Detection of deception with fMRI: Are we there yet? Legal and Criminological Psychology 13(1): 1–9.CrossRef
28.
Zurück zum Zitat Moreno, J.A. 2009. The future of neuroimaged lie detection and the law. Akron Law Review 42: 717–734. Moreno, J.A. 2009. The future of neuroimaged lie detection and the law. Akron Law Review 42: 717–734.
29.
Zurück zum Zitat Phelps, E. 2009. Lying outside the laboratory: The impact of imagery and emotion on the neural circuitry of lie detection. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 14–22. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Phelps, E. 2009. Lying outside the laboratory: The impact of imagery and emotion on the neural circuitry of lie detection. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 14–22. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
30.
Zurück zum Zitat Rakoff, J.S. 2009. Lie detection in the courts: The vain search for the magic bullet. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 40–45. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Rakoff, J.S. 2009. Lie detection in the courts: The vain search for the magic bullet. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 40–45. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
31.
Zurück zum Zitat Schauer, F. 2010. Can bad science be good evidence: Lie detection, neuroscience, and the mistaken conflation of legal and scientific norms. Cornell Law Review, forthcoming. Schauer, F. 2010. Can bad science be good evidence: Lie detection, neuroscience, and the mistaken conflation of legal and scientific norms. Cornell Law Review, forthcoming.
32.
Zurück zum Zitat Sinnott-Armstrong, W., et al. 2009. Neural lie detection in courts. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 35–39. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences. Sinnott-Armstrong, W., et al. 2009. Neural lie detection in courts. In Using imaging to identify deceit: Scientific and ethical questions, ed. Emilio Bizzi et al., 35–39. Cambridge: American Academy of ARts and Sciences.
33.
Zurück zum Zitat Spence, S. 2008. Playing devil’s advocate: The case against fMRI lie detection. Legal and Criminological Psychology 13(1): 11–25.CrossRef Spence, S. 2008. Playing devil’s advocate: The case against fMRI lie detection. Legal and Criminological Psychology 13(1): 11–25.CrossRef
34.
Zurück zum Zitat Henig, R.M. 2006. Looking for the lie. New York Times Magazine. February 5, 2006. Henig, R.M. 2006. Looking for the lie. New York Times Magazine. February 5, 2006.
35.
Zurück zum Zitat Narayan, A. 2009. The fMRI brain scan: A better lie detector? TIME Magazine. Narayan, A. 2009. The fMRI brain scan: A better lie detector? TIME Magazine.
36.
Zurück zum Zitat Silberman, S. 2006. Don’t even think about lying. Wired 14.01. Silberman, S. 2006. Don’t even think about lying. Wired 14.01.
37.
Zurück zum Zitat Wittgenstein, L. 1965. Preliminary studies for the “philosophical investigations”, generally known as the blue and brown books. New York: Harper & Row. Wittgenstein, L. 1965. Preliminary studies for the “philosophical investigations”, generally known as the blue and brown books. New York: Harper & Row.
38.
Zurück zum Zitat Caraway, C. 1986. Criteria and conceptual change in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Metaphilosophy 17(2): 162–171.CrossRef Caraway, C. 1986. Criteria and conceptual change in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Metaphilosophy 17(2): 162–171.CrossRef
39.
Zurück zum Zitat Klagge, J. 1989. Wittgenstein and neuroscience. Synthese 78(3): 319–343.CrossRef Klagge, J. 1989. Wittgenstein and neuroscience. Synthese 78(3): 319–343.CrossRef
40.
Zurück zum Zitat Koethe, J.L. 1977. The role of criteria in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7(3): 601–622. Koethe, J.L. 1977. The role of criteria in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7(3): 601–622.
41.
Zurück zum Zitat Albritton, R. 1959. On Wittgenstein’s use of the term ‘criterion’. Journal of Philosophy 56: 845–857.CrossRef Albritton, R. 1959. On Wittgenstein’s use of the term ‘criterion’. Journal of Philosophy 56: 845–857.CrossRef
42.
Zurück zum Zitat Caraway, C. 1984. Criteria and circumstances. The Southern Journal of Philosophy XXII(3): 307–316.CrossRef Caraway, C. 1984. Criteria and circumstances. The Southern Journal of Philosophy XXII(3): 307–316.CrossRef
43.
Zurück zum Zitat Chihara, C.S., and J.A. Fodor. 1965. Operationalism and ordinary language: A critique of Wittgenstein. American Philosophical Quarterly 2: 281–295. Chihara, C.S., and J.A. Fodor. 1965. Operationalism and ordinary language: A critique of Wittgenstein. American Philosophical Quarterly 2: 281–295.
44.
Zurück zum Zitat Garver, N. 1962. Wittgenstein on criteria. In Knowledge and experience, ed. C.D. Rollins, 55–87. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Garver, N. 1962. Wittgenstein on criteria. In Knowledge and experience, ed. C.D. Rollins, 55–87. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
45.
Zurück zum Zitat Hollinger, R. 1974. Natural kinds, family resemblances, and conceptual change. The Personalist 55: 323–332. Hollinger, R. 1974. Natural kinds, family resemblances, and conceptual change. The Personalist 55: 323–332.
46.
Zurück zum Zitat Kenny, A. 1967. Criterion. Encyclopedia of Philosophy 260–261. Kenny, A. 1967. Criterion. Encyclopedia of Philosophy 260–261.
47.
Zurück zum Zitat Malcolm, N. 1957. Dreaming. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Malcolm, N. 1957. Dreaming. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
48.
Zurück zum Zitat Putnam, H. 1962. Dreaming and ‘depth grammar’. In Analytical philosophy, ed. R.J. Butler, 211–235. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Putnam, H. 1962. Dreaming and ‘depth grammar’. In Analytical philosophy, ed. R.J. Butler, 211–235. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
49.
Zurück zum Zitat Scriven, M. 1959. The logic of criteria. Journal of Philosophy 56: 857–868.CrossRef Scriven, M. 1959. The logic of criteria. Journal of Philosophy 56: 857–868.CrossRef
50.
Zurück zum Zitat Lycan, W.G. 1971. Noninductive evidence: Recent work on Wittgenstein’s “criteria”. American Philosophical Quarterly 8(2): 109–125. Lycan, W.G. 1971. Noninductive evidence: Recent work on Wittgenstein’s “criteria”. American Philosophical Quarterly 8(2): 109–125.
51.
Zurück zum Zitat Knobe, J. 2007. Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance. Philosophical Explorations 10(2): 119–121.CrossRef Knobe, J. 2007. Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance. Philosophical Explorations 10(2): 119–121.CrossRef
52.
Zurück zum Zitat Knobe, J., and S. Nichols. 2008. An experimental philosophy manifesto. In Experimental philosophy, ed. J. Knobe and S. Nichols, 1–14. New York: Oxford University Press. Knobe, J., and S. Nichols. 2008. An experimental philosophy manifesto. In Experimental philosophy, ed. J. Knobe and S. Nichols, 1–14. New York: Oxford University Press.
53.
Zurück zum Zitat Nadelhoffer, T., and E. Nahmias. 2007. The past and future of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10(2): 123–149.CrossRef Nadelhoffer, T., and E. Nahmias. 2007. The past and future of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10(2): 123–149.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Neural Lie Detection, Criterial Change, and OrdinaryLanguage
verfasst von
Thomas Nadelhoffer
Publikationsdatum
01.11.2011
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Neuroethics / Ausgabe 3/2011
Print ISSN: 1874-5490
Elektronische ISSN: 1874-5504
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9080-6

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3/2011

Neuroethics 3/2011 Zur Ausgabe

Leitlinien kompakt für die Neurologie

Mit medbee Pocketcards sicher entscheiden.

Seit 2022 gehört die medbee GmbH zum Springer Medizin Verlag

Hirnblutung unter DOAK und VKA ähnlich bedrohlich

17.05.2024 Direkte orale Antikoagulanzien Nachrichten

Kommt es zu einer nichttraumatischen Hirnblutung, spielt es keine große Rolle, ob die Betroffenen zuvor direkt wirksame orale Antikoagulanzien oder Marcumar bekommen haben: Die Prognose ist ähnlich schlecht.

Thrombektomie auch bei großen Infarkten von Vorteil

16.05.2024 Ischämischer Schlaganfall Nachrichten

Auch ein sehr ausgedehnter ischämischer Schlaganfall scheint an sich kein Grund zu sein, von einer mechanischen Thrombektomie abzusehen. Dafür spricht die LASTE-Studie, an der Patienten und Patientinnen mit einem ASPECTS von maximal 5 beteiligt waren.

Schwindelursache: Massagepistole lässt Otholiten tanzen

14.05.2024 Benigner Lagerungsschwindel Nachrichten

Wenn jüngere Menschen über ständig rezidivierenden Lagerungsschwindel klagen, könnte eine Massagepistole der Auslöser sein. In JAMA Otolaryngology warnt ein Team vor der Anwendung hochpotenter Geräte im Bereich des Nackens.

Schützt Olivenöl vor dem Tod durch Demenz?

10.05.2024 Morbus Alzheimer Nachrichten

Konsumieren Menschen täglich 7 Gramm Olivenöl, ist ihr Risiko, an einer Demenz zu sterben, um mehr als ein Viertel reduziert – und dies weitgehend unabhängig von ihrer sonstigen Ernährung. Dafür sprechen Auswertungen zweier großer US-Studien.

Update Neurologie

Bestellen Sie unseren Fach-Newsletter und bleiben Sie gut informiert.